Werner Ulrich's Home Page:  Ulrich's Bimonthly

Formerly "Picture of the Month"

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

November-December 2014
The Rational, the Moral, and the General: An Exploration
Part 5: Ideas in Ancient Indian Thought / Analysis

   Ulrich's Bimonthly

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

An "Eastern" perspective: three ancient Indian ideas (continued) In the previous essay, we familiarized ourselves with the world of ideas of the Vedic tradition of ancient Indian philosophy and particularly with the Upanishads. The present second essay focuses on three concepts that play an important role in the Upanishads and also appear particularly interesting from a methodological point of view: brahman, atman, and jagat. Like earlier essays in this series, this one and its sequels are again structured into "Intermediate Reflections," to emphasize the exploratory character of the considerations in question. The first of these (and sixth overall), which makes up the present essay, analyzes the meaning of the three concepts as they are employed in the Upanishads. A subsequent reflection, which will be offered in the next Bimonthly, will discuss a specific example in the form of one of the most famous verses of the Upanishads. Two later reflections, planned for the final part of the series, will be dedicated to a complementary, language-analytical view of the Upanishads and to the question of what we can learn from Upanishadic thought, and particularly from the three core ideas we analyzed, about the proper use of general ideas today.

Sixth intermediate reflection:
Three essential ideas of ancient Indian thought

A caveat  Before we consider the etymology and meaning of the three concepts of brahman, atman, and jagat, a word of caution is in order. Being thoroughly grounded in a Western, Kantian tradition of thought, I do not assume that with some fragmentary (though careful) reading of English translations of ancient Indian texts, combined with some introductory accounts and commentaries, it is possible to gain a sufficient understanding of the entirely different tradition of thought in which they originate, the Vedic tradition. I accept the cautionary words of Müller (1879), who in the Preface to his translation of the Upanishads notes that there are three basic obstacles to understanding these ancient "sacred texts of the East," as he calls them, from a modern Western perspective:

I must begin this series of translations of the Sacred Books of the East with three cautions:--the first, referring to the character of the original texts here translated; the second, with regard to the difficulties in making a proper use of translations; the third, showing what is possible and what is impossible in rendering ancient thought into modern speech. (Müller, 1879, p. ix)

In short, we must never forget that deep-seated differences of culture, language, and epoch create a distance to these ancient texts that is difficult to overcome, certainly for a Western mind. As a result of all three difficulties, particularly the first, Müller notes that the Upanishads, along with their bright and illuminating sides, also have their "dark" (1879, p. xi) and at times "almost unintelligible" (1879, p. xiv) sides. They can tell us much about "the dawn of religious consciousness of man," something that "must always remain one of the most inspiring and hallowing sights in the whole history of the world" (1879, p. xi); but there is also "much that is strange and startling, … tedious … or repulsive, or, lastly, … difficult to construe and to understand." (1879, p. xii) If an eminent scholar like Müller feels compelled to avow of such difficulties and limitations in studying the Upanishads, it should be clear from the outset (and I want to leave no doubts) that my reading of some of these texts can only provide a very limited understanding; limited, that is, by my current interest in the role of general ideas within the Western tradition of rational ethics. My interest is a methodological rather than a metaphysical one, much less a religious one. The aim is to develop the notion of a "critically contextualist" handling of general ideas, and it is within this context that what I'll say about the three Upanishadic concepts of "brahman," "atman," and "jagat" should be understood and used. For once, the (limited) end of my undertaking hopefully justifies the (equally limited) means. With this cautionary remark in mind, let us now turn to the three selected concepts.

Three essential Upanishadic ideas: brahman, atman, and jagat

"Brahman" The major theme of all Vedanta texts and particularly of the Upanishads is the human endeavor of seeking knowledge of brahman, the ultimate, unchanging, and infinite reality that lies beyond all limitations of the phenomenal world, although it also manifests itself in it as well as in the human individual's innermost consciousness and spirituality, the "self." Brahman thus embodies the notion of both a transcendent and an immanent reality. As a transcendent reality, its essence is prior to and "beyond all distinctions or forms" (Easwaran, 2007, p. 339); accordingly we cannot grasp it in our perceptions and descriptions of the world. As an immanent reality, it nevertheless permeates or, as the Upanishads put it, “dwells in” these perceptions and descriptions; accordingly we cannot properly understand what they mean unless we understand them as imperfect and fragmentary expressions of that other, larger or higher reality that is not accessible to us in any direct and objective way.

In the more analytical terms used earlier, we might also understand brahman to embody the universe of second-order knowledge, the conceptual tools and efforts without which we cannot adequately understand our first-order knowledge, that is, more accurately, the manifold particular universes within which the individual’s perceptions, thoughts, and actions move at any time. Among such second-order devices I would count the main subject of this series of essays, general ideas and principles of reason, along with categories of knowable things, modalities of meaningful statements, forms of valid inferences or arguments, and other concepts that enable us to think and talk clearly about our first-order knowledge and its limitations.

Root meanings  The word “brahman” (from the Sanskrit root brh-, "to swell, expand, grow, increase") is basically a neuter noun that stands for an abstract concept of the universe – the ground of all being – rather than for a personification of its divine originator. However, the latter interpretation can also be found (e.g., in the Isha Upanishad) and the word can then, as in a few other specific meanings, take the masculine gender. In between an entirely impersonal and a personified notion lies a third frequent understanding of brahman, as the one universal spirit or soul that is thought to inhere the entire universe and thus also the human spirit. Forth and finally, since there is no sharp distinction between the knowledge that an enlightened person is seeking to acquire and the sources of such knowledge, the term brahman can also be found historically to stand for the sacred texts or, in the previous oral tradition, the sacred words that reveal the knowledge in question. If there is a common denominator of these various, partly metaphysical and partly religious meanings, we might see it in the notion that brahman is always that which needs to be studied on the path to enlightenment – yet another reference to second-order knowledge, in the analytical terms adopted in the previous essay.

This is obviously a highly simplified account of the etymology of the brahman concept, given that the major Sanskrit-English dictionary of Monier-Williams (1899, p. 737f, and 1872, pp. 689 and 692f; cf. Cologne Project, 1997/2008 and 2013/14, also Monier-Williams et al., 2008) lists no less than some 27 meanings of brahman. Table 1 offers a selection and also highlights some of the meanings of most interest here.

Table 1: Selected meanings of brahman

Source: Monier-Williams, 1899, 737f and 741, and 1872, pp. 689, 692f, abridged and simplified

brahman (in Sanskrit script) brahman, bráhman, n[euter gender].

(lit. "growth," "expansion," "evolution," "development," "swelling of the spirit or soul"), from brih, pious effusion or utterance, outpouring of the heart in worshipping the gods, prayer.

the sacred word (as opp. to vac, the word of man), the veda, a sacred text, a text or mantra used as a spell [read: magic formula]; the sacred syllable Om.

the brAhmaNa portion of the veda.

religious or spiritual knowledge (opp. to religious observances and bodily mortification such as tapas).

holy life (esp. continence, chastity; cf. brahma-carya).

(exceptionally treated as m.) the brahma or [the] one self-existent impersonal Spirit,
the one universal Soul (or one divine essence and source from which all created things emanate or with which they are identified and to which they return), the Self-existent, the Absolute, the Eternal (not generally an object of worship, but rather of meditation and knowledge).

bráhman, n[euter gender]. the class of men who are the repositories and communicators of sacred knowledge, the Brahmanical caste as a body (rarely an individual Brahman).

wealth; final emancipation.

brahmán, m[asculine gender]. one who prays, a devout or religious man, a Bráhman who is a knower of Vedic texts or spells, one versed in sacred knowledge.

the intellect (=buddhi).

one of the four principal priests or ritvijas; the brahman was the most learned of them and was required to know the three vedas, to supervise the sacrifice and to set right mistakes; at a later period his functions were based especially on the atharva-veda).

brahmA, m[asculine gender]. the one impersonal universal Spirit manifested as a personal Creator and as the first of the triad of personal gods (he never appears to have become an object of general worship, though he has two temples in India).

brAhma, n[eutral gender]. the one self-existent Spirit, the Absolute.

sacred study, the study of the Vedas.

brAhma, m[asculine gender]. a priest.

brAhma, mf [masculine or feminine gender]. relating to sacred knowledge, prescribed by the Vedas, scriptural; sacred to the Vedas; relating or belonging to the brahmans or the sacerdotal class.

brahmin, mfn [masculine, feminine or neutral gender]. belonging or relating to brahman or brahmA; possessing sacred knowledge.

Copyleft  copy left  2014 W. Ulrich

Derived meanings The neuter noun brahman should not be confused with its masculine versions, which are also written "brahmin" and "Brahmana." A brahmin or a brahmán (as a masculine noun) is "a knower of Vedic texts" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 738; Macdonnell, 1929, p. 193); a devout man, priest or spiritual teacher (guru) "versed in sacred texts" (1872, p. 689); a seeker on the path to knowledge of brahman (brahmavidya) who usually is also a member of the brahmanic caste. The term can also stand for the caste itself, as "the class of men who are the repositories and communicators of sacred knowledge" (1899, p. 738), in which case it is used in the neuter gender. Further, the noun brahma (except as part of compounds) should be distinguished from brahman; in the neuter gender it stands for a personification of brahman that is conceived in a rather abstract way, as a universal consciousness or "universal spirit" that manifests itself in the world and in the human individual. There are also a number of derivative meanings (partly used in composite terms such as bramavidya or bramacarya, the study and practice of brahmanic knowledge) in which the term often takes the masculine or (rarely) the feminine gender and designates either the "sacred knowledge" of the Vedas or the person who possesses it. In contemporary, post-Vedic (and thus also post-Vedantic) Hindu religion, finally, brahma is now often also understood as referring to a personal creator-God and as such is worshipped as the main god in the divine trinity (or trimurti) of Brahma, Vishnu, and Shiva, an understanding that is not, however, characteristic of Upanishadic thought.

Personal reading  The concept of primary interest to us is the abstract, impersonal notion of brahman as an invisible reality that lies beyond, yet informs, all we can perceive and say about the world, a "source from which all created things emanate" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 737, similarly 1872, p. 689) and which accordingly we would need to understand so as to ensure reliable knowledge and proper action. Navlakha (2000) nicely summarizes this non-religious, philosophical understanding:

Brahman as the absolute reality is purely impersonal, and is not to be confused with a personal God. The significance of brahman is metaphysical, not theological. Brahman is the featureless absolute, which unless a contextual necessity otherwise demands, is most appropriately referred to as 'It'. [Which is to say, the] brahman of the Upanishads is also not to be seen as the Creator God, as in Judaeo-Christian tradition. There is no creation as such in Vedanta. The universe is evolved out of brahman. [… ] Thus brahman is the one and only cause of the coming into existence of the universe. Brahman is whole and unfolds itself out in the form of the universe, out of its own substance, and as a means of knowing itself. […] Thus there is nothing, not even the minutest part of the material world, that is not wholly brahman. Within and without, it is all brahman. (Navlakha, 2000, p. xviiif)

For our present purpose, I take it indeed that "the significance of brahman is metaphysical, not theological." As a metaphysical concept, brahman designates a realm of reality that lies both "within and without" our awareness of the world. We cannot grasp it in any direct way, but it informs our personal world and at the same time can take us beyond it. It is described as a "whole" (all-encompassing) universe in that no-one can claim to stand outside of it, and as "featureless" (unfathomable, beyond description) in that whatever ideas we make ourselves of it, they reflect our own projections rather than objective reality. But why, readers will wonder, should we be interested at all in such an ancient piece of metaphysics?

As we said earlier, what matters from a methodological point of view is not that we avoid metaphysics (an impossible feat) but rather, how we handle it; that is, what kind of questions it makes us ask. If metaphysical assumptions are unavoidable, we can as well try to rely on a metaphysical framework that makes us ask relevant questions. It's not that today we would want to adopt this ancient piece of metaphysics but rather, that understanding it allows us to appreciate the more critical side of Upanishadic thought. Seen in this way, the Upanishadic metaphysics of "this" and "that" reality (compare the earlier characterization in the introductory essay, see Ulrich, 2014c, pp. 11-15 and 18) is not a bad starting point. It reminds us of the second-order knowledge that is implicit in all first-order knowledge, and thus of the need for questioning the ways in which our knowledge – or what we take for it – depends on such second-order assumptions. The Upanishadic difference between "this" and "that" creates distance, and thus a basis for such reflection. It makes it clear that we don't really (sic) understand this world of ours, or what we believe to know about it, unless we reflect on that larger universe – that fuller reality – of which it (and our supposed knowledge of it) is part.

Well-understood metaphysics invites critique. This becomes obvious as soon as, in the quote above, we understand the phrase "all created things" to include our individual and social constructions of reality, as well as our propositions about, and actions in, this world of ours, along with the ideational universe that informs them. The critique required then clearly includes methodological reflection about the ways we construct our notions of reality. By what kinds of conceptual constructs do we try to make the reality we perceive intelligible and meaningful and to turn it into "our" reality? And if people rely on different constructs to frame their realities, which views or conceptions of reality should "really" count as true knowledge and might then also inform rational action? We begin to see the methodological point: without the conception of some ultimate, universal reality behind and beyond our individual realities, we face a bottomless pluralism and relativism of what is to count as true and rational. Brahman tells us how inadequate our individual realities are and how much we consequently depend on questioning them and trying to find some mutual understanding about them with others.

In this respect, parallels may well be drawn between Upanishadic and Kantian thought. Both rely on metaphysical assumptions; in both cases these are conducive to epistemological and methodological considerations that are far from being irrelevant to our epoch, in that they are apt to question prevailing conceptions of knowledge and rationality. I will discuss two examples in a moment, concerning the unsatisfactory ways in which these conceptions deal with the issues of holism and of subjectivity; but first we need to deepen our understanding a little further of how metaphysical assumptions can give rise to methodological reflection.

Metaphysics and methodology  Returning for a moment to the parallels between Kant's concepts of pure reason and a non-religious concept of brahman, we face in both cases ideas that exceed the reach of ordinary human knowledge and insofar are bound to remain problematic; at the same time, again in both cases, we recognize that reasonable thought cannot do without some ideas of this kind. Both can therefore also provide impetus for a more than merely superficial critique of knowledge. For example, as we found in our earlier discussion of Kant's understanding of general ideas (see Ulrich, 2014a, "Third intermediate reflection"), we cannot think of a series of conditions that would explain any specific phenomenon of interest, without also thinking of an ultimate, unconditioned condition. As Kant (1787, B444) puts it, "for a given conditioned, the whole series of conditions subordinated to each other is likewise given"; but that "whole series" (i.e., totality) of conditions is itself unconditioned, as otherwise it would depend on some further condition and thus could not furnish a complete explanation (cf. 1787, B379, B383f, B444 and B445n). In short, explanations that really explain anything will always reach beyond the experiential world of conditioned phenomena. Of necessity they include general ideas that refer us to some unconditioned whole of conditions, which is what Kant means by pure concepts of reason. "Concepts of reason contain the unconditioned." (1787, B367). Likewise, in the Upanishads, when brahman is said to stand for the "ground of all being" or "source from which all created things emanate" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 738), or is described as the "one," "ultimate" and "absolute" (i.e., unconditioned) reality that lies behind people's multiple realities, such a notion amounts no less to an unavoidable idea of reason than does Kant's notion of a totality of conditions that is itself unconditioned.

Metaphysics and methodology are close siblings here. The methodological significance of brahman for the practice of reason shines through in many metaphysical characterizations, both in the Upanishads themselves and in the secondary literature. As an illustration from the Upanishads, there is this famous prayer in the Brihadaranyaka Upanishad in which the devotee seeks guidance on the search for reality and self-realization:

Lead me from the unreal to the real!
Lead me from darkness to light!
Lead me from death to immortality!

(Brihadaranyaka Upanishad, 1.3.28, as transl. by Müller and Navlakha, 2000, p. 76, similarly Olivelle, 1996, p. 12f)

That is to say, truth is not of this world; reality is not to be found in the phenomenal world. Our human "real world" is deceptive, a source of darkness rather than light. It obscures rather than illuminates that basic source of insight that is called brahman and which is the only reliable source of orientation for proper thought and action.

This Upanishadic explanation of the real world's deceptiveness is metaphysical, but not therefore methodologically irrelevant. In fact, its methodological implications are largely equivalent to those of Kant's similar conception of a noumenal (i.e., intelligible, ideational) world as distinguished from the phenomenal (observable, experiential) world. Both pairs of concepts are about our notion of reality, that is, they rely on metaphysical assumptions that obviously remain open to challenge. Both frameworks also handle their assumptions in a critically self-reflective fashion; they do not claim that the metaphysical is knowable. Nor do they fall into the trap of metaphysical dualism, which would mean to treat "this" and "that" (or the phenomenal and the noumenal) as substantially separate entities. Rather, the metaphysical assumptions in question function as calls to a discipline of critical self-reflection on the part of the knowing subject. They represent critical reminders, not presumptions of knowledge. Interestingly, the two frameworks share this critical orientation although they differ in the ways they understand and handle their metaphysical underpinnings: while for the Upanishadic thinkers, brahman is a symbol of the objective world that is ineffable but real, as opposed to the phenomenal world's deceptiveness, Kant's Critique does not of course permit any reification of the noumenal world; he understands it as a transcendental (i.e., methodological) rather than transcendent (i.e., metaphysical) concept. Kant thus puts the relationship of the noumenal (metaphysical) and the phenomenal (experiential) – of "that" and "this" world – on its head: it is not the absolute and universal (and for some, the esoteric) but the empirical and particular (the exoteric) which for Kant constitutes "reality." Still, the methodological challenge remains: for Kant, too, there is no such thing as a direct access to reality, for the empirical is always already informed by our cognitive apparatus or, in Kant's more precise terms, by reason's a priori categories and ideas. Both frameworks, then, live up to the demand of reason that we formulated above: "well-understood metaphysics invites critique."

As another illustration, this time from the secondary literature, let us consider one of those many descriptions of brahman that are reminiscent of Kant's recognition of the unavoidability of the idea of a totality of conditions that is itself unconditioned (the basic principle of reason). In his Fundamentals of Indian Philosophy, Puligandla (1977, p. 222) describes brahman as an "unchanging reality amidst and beyond the world" (my italics). The "amidst" is apt to remind us that whenever we try to explain some real-world phenomena, we have always already presupposed that there is a complete series of conditions – perhaps also some fundamental, unifying force or principle – that would indeed allow us to explain the conditioned nature of things the ways we customarily do it and rely upon, whether in science or philosophy, in everyday argumentation or practical action. Whether such a reliable, sufficient ground of explanation exists indeed and how it would have to be defined and proven (i.e., explained, an impossibility by definition), we ultimately have no way to tell. But then again, methodology, unlike metaphysics, can do without pretending such metaphysical knowledge. It is quite sufficient for methodological purposes to recognize that what we can know empirically (the phenomenal world) is not identical with reality and conversely, that the real lies at least partly beyond the phenomenal and therefore also beyond knowledge. Recognizing a lack of knowledge can be a basis for compelling methodological reflections and conclusions.

Neither in Upanishadic nor in Kantian thought we depend on an ontological proof of some last conditions to deal appropriately with the conditioned nature of all we can observe, think, and claim to know. What matters is to recognize that without assuming (which is not the same as proving) a whole series of conditions that is complete, we cannot think and talk clearly about our knowledge of the world and its limitations. At the same time, as we can never demonstrate the reality of a sufficient set of conditions, our practices of inquiry and argumentation need to handle the situation accordingly. The Upanishadic way of envisioning such an assumed, sufficient set of conditions is brahman, and its way of handling the situation is by "seeking to know brahman" – or, to put it more carefully, by seeking to get closer to knowing brahman – for instance, through meditative and mystical means; through a discipline of self-reflection and self-limitation; and ultimately through one's entire practice of life.

As is to be expected in view of brahman's ineffable nature, the Upanishads and their commentators suggest many different descriptions of it. Still, if we are to believe the Encyclopaedia Britannica, "they concur in the definition of brahman as eternal, conscious, irreducible, infinite, omnipresent, spiritual source of the universe of finiteness and change." (Encyclopaedia Britannica, 2013b) In the light of what we just said, such a definition must look excessively metaphysical. To do justice to the Encyclopaedia, it mirrors the language of the Upanishads and of most commentators. No faithful account of the Upanishads can entirely avoid explaining them in their own terms, so readers will also find some metaphysical language in my continuing account. As the discussion thus far should have illustrated, this circumstance need not stop us from focusing on methodological considerations. While metaphysical considerations are about the nature of reality (i.e., ontology), methodological questioning as I understand it is about the proper use of reason (i.e., rationality) in pursuing theoretical or practical ends. Instead of complaining about the metaphysical character of the Upanishads, we can make a difference by analyzing what they have to tell us about the proper use of reason. Why not try to do this from a critical, contemporary perspective, while still trying to remain faithful to the language, spirit and wisdom of these ancient texts?

The proper use of reason and the quest for practical excellence  The proposed methodological interest in the Upanishads is quite compatible, I think, with their essential orientation towards the practical: in Upanishadic thought, the study of brahman matters as much for mastering our lives as for purely speculative reasons. Remember what we said in the introductory essay about the importance of concepts such as svadharma (one's individual dharma or "law) and karma (from karman = work, action, performance; one's record of good deeds which is effective as cause of one's future fate). Their essential, practical concern is to guide us in developing right thought and conduct on the path to individual self-realization. Similar observations could be made about the implications of such concepts for professional self-realization, for example, by cultivating high standards of excellence in one's practices of inquiry, consultancy, and other uses of professional expertise. The quest for practical excellence requires no less an effort of self-reflection and self-limitation, along with clear and consistent reasoning, than does the search for theoretical understanding.

As always, such demands are more easily formulated than put into practice. In practice, they face us with considerable difficulties. Specifically, as we have emphasized with reference to Kant, the proper use of reason depends on considering all the circumstances that might be relevant, not just those that present themselves immediately and/or conform to our private interests. Whether for practical or theoretical ends – a distinction that the Upanishads do not draw as sharply as we tend to do it nowadays – the need for maintaining the integrity of reason entails a need for comprehensiveness with respect to the conditions or circumstances we take into account. Any other kind of account of situations and what might be done about them is not only potentially deceptive but also arbitrary, in that it relies on selections of relevant circumstances that remain unconsidered, if not undeclared and unsubstantiated. On the other hand, complete rationality is obviously beyond our capabilities, both in thought and in action. We are well advised to strive for it, but not to claim it. This is the basic philosophical dilemma with which the Upanishadic demand of "seeking to know brahman" confronts us: the simultaneous need for, and unavailability of, an objective and comprehensive grasp of reality beyond the ways it manifests itself to us or interests us privately, whether in everyday life or in situations of professional intervention. In Upanishadic terms, to understand this world of ours we must also strive to comprehend that other world which lies beyond it but is part of the total reality.

The better one understands this dilemma involved in the proper use of reason, and thus also in the search for practical excellence, the more one will appreciate the often mystic and poetic (rather than strictly philosophical) approach of the Upanishads. To understand our daily world of experience and action, they tell us, we need to develop a discipline of seeking distance (the discipline involved in seeking to know brahman). Distance, that is, from our usual ways of being situated in the world, which prevent us from seeing "situations" (i.e., individual or collective situatedness) as clearly and objectively as proper thought and action would require. What at first glance may look like an escape – a mere way of avoiding a philosophical difficulty – then becomes understandable as a methodically pertinent response: its point is practicing detachment from the world as it is apparently given, or from situations as they present themselves to us and raise in us egocentric and short-sighted concerns about them. Thus understood, the mystic and poetic-metaphysical language of the Upanishads carries a deeply philosophical message indeed. In essence, though perhaps not always in formulation and elaboration, this message is akin to that of Kant: knowledge, unless it is subject to the proper use of reason, is as much a source of error as it is a source of certainty.20)

The problem of holism  One of the traditional ways of framing the dilemma in Western philosophy is in terms of the problem of holism. Whatever we know, think, and say about the world, it is insufficient as measured by the latter's holistic nature. This methodological implication comes to the fore in the beautiful, at first rather mystical InvocationAn Upanishadic invocation (in Devanagari script) (i.e., an incantation, the chanting of magical words or formulas at the outset of a prayer or meditation) that introduces several of the Upanishads that belong to the Yajur Veda, among them the Brihadaranyaka, Isha, and Shvetashvatara Upanishads. I cite their identical invocation first in Sanskrit (in Devanagari script above and in Roman transliteration below) and then in three slightly different translations, all of which are customary in the literature.

om purnamadah purnamidam purnaat purnamudachyate
purnasya purnaamadaya purnameva vashishyate
om shanti shanti shanti

(Source: Swami J. [n.d.], http://www.swamij.com/upanishad-isha-purna.htm)

The key word purna is the perfect participle of the verb pur, which appears to be related to the English verb "to pour." It means as much as "poured out," "filled" or "full," and hence "complete," "whole," "entire," and more figuratively also "accomplished," "contented," "powerful," and so on (see Apte, 1890/2014, p. 715, and 1965/2008, pp. 14 and 139). In the following translations of the invocation, the initial and final magical words 'om' and 'shanti' are not repeated; note again the previously discussed, careful use of the terms "this" and "that" in all three versions.

All this is full. All that is full.
From fullness, fullness comes.
When fullness is taken from fullness, fullness still remains.”

(Invocations to the Isha, Brihadaranyaka and Shvetashvatara Upanishads, as transl. by Easwaran, 2007, pp. 56, 93, and 158; similarly transl. by Nikhilananda, 1949, p. 200, and 2003, pp. 86 and 254; note that in the Sanskrit text, "all that" comes before "all this," as is the case in the following translations)

That is whole, this is whole.
This whole proceeds from that whole.
On taking away this whole from that whole, it remains whole.

(Invocation to the Brihadaranyaka Upanishad, as transl. by Müller/Navlakha, 2000, p. xix)

That is infinite, this is infinite;
From that infinite this infinite comes.
From that infinite, this infinite removed or added, infinite remains infinite.

(Invocation to the Isha Upanishad, as cited, along with a selection of other customary translations, in the Yoga site of Swami J [n.d.].)

Indeed, in view of the infinite and transcendent nature of "that" world of brahman, which nevertheless inheres and conditions "this" finite but infinitely variable world of ours, need we not wonder how we may claim to understand anything without understanding the ways in which it relates to that larger, full reality of which it is a part? As both the Upanishads and Kant's ideas of reason make us understand, human reason needs this holistic notion of an all-inclusive whole as a reference point in relation to which it can situate its own perennially conditioned nature, its amounting to so much less than a comprehensive and objective grasp of things. At the same time, any such notion is bound to remain a problematic idea of reason. Holistic knowledge and understanding is a claim that cannot be redeemed argumentatively, whether based on logic or empirical inquiry or both. Logic tells us that we need it, but not what it is; and inquiry fails as the whole reaches beyond the empirical.

The Upanishadic thinkers understood this dilemma very clearly, some two and a half thousand years ago, before the disciplines of logic and epistemology were available to them. Their way of putting it was metaphysical and metaphorical, by means of the two great Upanishadic symbols (or metaphors) of human striving, atman, as the embodiment of individual self-knowledge and self-realization (a concept to which we will turn a little later), and brahman as the embodiment of proper universal knowledge, that is, understanding of the unity and perfection of the universe. Expressed in these terms, the problem of holism consists in the difficulty that atman cannot find brahman empirically in "this" world, through the means of inquiry, nor logically, through the means of inference. For the whole is not only beyond the empirical, it is also, as the Upanishads teach us, "one without a second," that is, unique (Chandogya, 6.2.1-2) and therefore beyond logic. There is no logic of uniqueness, no stringent inference from what we know empirically (i.e., particulars) to what is unique (i.e., universals). Both epistemologically and analytically, the universal lies beyond human knowledge. Still, reason cannot do without the notion of universal qualities and principles. It cannot renounce the quest for a full understanding of reality in such terms. Human striving for knowledge of brahman is therefore a meaningful and indispensable quest, although we should never assume that we have actually achieved it.

This, then, is the Upanishadic way of describing the methodological dilemma with which the problem of holism confronts us. To this day it has remained a classical dilemma in many fields of philosophy such as language analysis and semiotics, hermeneutics, epistemology, and practical philosophy, and also in my work on critical systems heuristics (CSH). In the terms of the Upanishads: atman needs to seek knowledge of brahman and yet must avoid any presumption of knowledge. Or, as I like to put it in the terms of CSH: "Holistic thinking – the quest for comprehensiveness – is a meaningful effort but not a meaningful claim." (Ulrich, 2012a, p. 1236; similarly in 2012b, p. 1314 and, as applied to the moral idea, in 2013a, p. 38) This situation has motivated my call for a “critical turn” of the contemporary understanding of competent inquiry and rational practice. The essential aim then becomes ensuring sufficient critique rather than sufficient justification of theoretical or practical claims. This is feasible because, as we said above, recognizing a lack of knowledge can be a basis for compelling methodological provisions. The methodological consequence is a need for what I call a “critical systems approach” to research and professional practice, that is, a framework that would provide methodological support to critically comprehensive thinking or, as I originally defined it in CSH, an approach that aims to "secure at least a critical solution to the problem of practical reason" (Ulrich, 1983, pp. 25, 34-37, 177, and passim).

The problem (and richness) of subjectivity A second methodological implication of the metaphysical concept of brahman concerns the importance of subjectivity. Once we have understood that human thought cannot do without assuming some ultimate, unconditional ground of all that exits – a totality of conditions that exists in an unconditional, absolute, perhaps objective way – we also begin to understand how limited and subjective all our perceptions of this world of ours are bound to be, amounting at best to glimpses of that underlying larger, infinite reality. It follows that whatever knowledge of things we can aspire to possess, it will be so much less than objective, as it can just grasp aspects of that which is "really" the case. The objective is elusive, for it would be all-inclusive.

Ganeri (2001, p. 1) succinctly speaks of brahman as "the Upanishadic symbol for objectivity itself," as opposed to "the subjectivity that goes along with being situated in the world." As the Mundaka Upanishad puts it, brahman stands for that all-encompassing, infinite reality in which everything else is rooted and "through which, if it is known, everything else becomes known" (Mundaka Upanishad, 1.1.3, as transl: by Müller, 1897/2000, p. 47, and Müller/Navlakha, 2000, p. xi; note that the latter source wrongly refers to Mundaka 1.1.4). As I would put it, the Upanishads can inspire in us the humility of accepting that there are limits to what we can hope to know and understand, due to our being situated in this world. Such awareness can encourage mutual tolerance, as well as reflective practice in the sense of paying attention to the ways in which people's individual situatedness may shape their views and values. Multiple, subjective views embody a richness of views that would not be attainable otherwise. They thus have intrinsic value in the quest for comprehensiveness, for seeking to better know brahman. Methodologically speaking, then, the situation is not quite as bad as it looks metaphysically. Although there are always limits to what as individuals we can claim to know, no specific limits are beyond questioning and expansion; and to this end, we can always listen and talk to others.

In the Upanishadic conception of inquiry, brahman furnishes the standard for such questioning. As the Upanishads admonish us time and again, we can "really" know and understand things only inasmuch as we know and understand them in their relation to brahman. Brahman, in the metaphysical terms of the Upanishads, is the conception of a reality that, because it is "self-existent" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 737f), is independent of any condition external to it. It thus mirrors, in our own discourse-theoretical terms, the ideal of a self-contained account of reality that could do without any reference to conditions outside its own universe of discourse and thus would be entirely true and reliable. As an ideal, it does not lend itself to realization; but it certainly provides impetus for critical thought – about the ways our accounts of reality fail to be self-contained and, worse, about our usual failure to limit our claims accordingly.

This is a conception of knowledge that is important indeed for our understanding of general ideas of reason. The parallels we encountered earlier between the Upanishadic concept of brahman as an absolute, all-inclusive, and infinite reality on the one hand, and Kant's concept of a totality of conditions (or an infinite series of conditions) that reason cannot help but presuppose on the other hand, are relevant here. Both concepts confront us with unavoidable limitations of human knowledge. Both therefore also imply the need for a discipline of self-reflection and self-limitation. But of course, there is also an important difference, in that the two traditions of thought have developed this discipline in entirely different directions – meditative spirituality and ascetism in the one tradition, critique of reason in the other. The deeper, underlying difference is that Kant makes us understand the totality of conditions as a methodological rather than metaphysical concept or, in his terms, as a transcendental rather than transcendent idea. Although a conventional, metaphysical and spiritual reading may well remain of primary importance to most people in studying the Upanishads, the mentioned parallels nevertheless suggest to me that a metaphysical reading can and should lead on to a critical study of what these ancient texts have to tell us about present-day notions of knowledge, science, and rationality, as well as about the roles we give these notions in modern societies. For example, such a reading might encourage a critique of science that reaches deeper than current notions of reflective practice in science and professional practice. Such critique in turn might provide new impetus for the necessary discourse on how contemporary conceptions of science-theory, research philosophy, theory of knowledge, and practical philosophy could be developed so as to overcome the crisis of rationality to which I briefly referred at the outset (Ulrich, 2013c, p. 1).

With a view to such a methodological reading and study of the Upanishads, I would argue – drawing on our previous examinations of the nature and use of ideas of reason in Parts 2 and 3 – that brahman is properly understood as a limiting concept, that is, as a projected endpoint towards which we can direct reflection on what we take to represent valid knowledge and rational practice. We have discussed the notion of ideas as limiting concepts or projected endpoints of thought earlier (see Ulrich, 2014a, p. 7 and note 5, and 2014b, pp. 23-28); suffice it to recall that reason needs such notions as reference points for its critical business, however problematic they are bound to remain due to their exceeding the reach of possible knowledge. They thus pose a double challenge to reason. Reason needs to employ them for critical ends while at the same time learning to handle them critically, that is, to keep a critical stance towards any claims based on their use. Again, as with the striking parallels we observed before, I see no essential methodological difference in this regard between the Upanishads' brahman and Kant's ideas of reason. Consequently, a further conjecture offers itself: we might try to embed Upanishadic reflection on knowledge as inspired by the notion of brahman – "brahmanic reflection" as it were – in the same kind of double or cyclical movement of critical thought with which we earlier associated the pragmatic use or "approximation" of Kant's ideas of reason, equally understood as limiting concepts. The idea is that in this way we might gain a deeper understanding of both, the movement of critical thought in question as well as the methodological implications of the "brahmanic reflection" just suggested. So much for a brief outlook. At present we are not yet prepared for such a discussion, as we first need to familiarize ourselves with the two other Upanishadid ideas that we selected for examination, atman and jagat.

"Atman" A second major theme is atman, a counter-concept to brahman inasmuch as it focuses on the individual that seeks to know or experience brahman, rather than on brahman itself. Atman stands for the subjective side of the quest for knowing brahman. If brahman is the Upanishadic symbol for objectivity, atman is the symbol for subjectivity. Or, in the terms we used in the introductory essay, atman embodies the emerging knowing subject of the Upanishads, whose search for understanding what is real and reliable in this ever-changing world – where to find that basic, unchanging reality called brahman – leads it to discover its own consciousness and self-reflection. "Atman, or the Self, is the consciousness, the knowing subject, within us." (Nikhilananda, 1949, p. 52). As the Upanishadic thinkers understood centuries before the early thinkers of the Occident (e.g., the pre-Socratic philosophers of nature, such as Anaxagoras and Democritus, and later Plato and Aristotle), the key to understanding our (for ever imperfect) grasp of the objective world lies in ourselves, in our consciousness and, as a contemporary Western perspective might want to add, in our individual and collective unconscious or subconscious (see Jung, 1966, 1968a). Early on the ancient Indian sages understood that both brahman and atman – the objective and the subjective principle – are indispensable notions for reflecting on the sources and nature of human knowledge or error, even if both notions are ultimately beyond human grasp. Likewise, they recognized that neither notion is independent of the other; each manifests itself in the other but cannot be reduced to it. "The Absolute of the Upanishads manifests itself as the subject as well as the object and transcends them both." (Sharma, 2000, p. 25).

Root meanings  The word atman quite obviously contains the Sanskrit root of the contemporary German verb atmen = to breathe; compare the German masculine noun der Atem = breath, a word that in contemporary German is still also used in metaphoric or spiritual expressions such as der Atem Gottes, meaning the creative presence of God's spirit. The Sanskrit atman in turn appears to be derived not only from the root "at" (= to move, go constantly, walk, run, as in Atem; cf. Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 24) but also from the second root "an" (= to breathe, live, as in the Latin noun animus for spirit or soul; cf. Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 12). The two root meanings come together in the act of breathing in and out. Note that for phonological or declensional reasons, the initial "a" in atman is suppressed in some uses, yielding 'tman. This happens frequently when the term appears in compound words following a vowel. Employing the phonetically reduced form along with the complete form may help in consulting the Sanskrit dictionaries, but otherwise need not concern us here.

Table 2 lists the entries of Monier-Williams (1899) for both forms. Readers wishing to verify these entries may like to know that the on-line search tools of the Cologne Project (1997/2008 and 2013/14) and Monier-Williams et al. (2008) currently only list tman and under this entry do not include all the meanings given in the original dictionary for atman; the latter are accessible through the online facsimile edition listed in the reference section under Monier-Williams (1899). Easier to use and more complete in this respect are some of the other Sanskrit dictionaries, particularly Apte (1965/2008) and, with some reservations regarding completeness, Böhtlingk and Roth (1855, p. 3-3f) and Böthlingk and Schmidt (1879/1928, p. 3-045). For reasons of consistency, Table 2, like the previous Table 1 (for "brahman") and the later Table 3 (for "jagat"), relies on Monier-Williams and focuses on the root meanings of "atman"; some of Apte's additional translations will be mentioned in the subsequent text. As in the case of Table 1, I have again highlighted some of the meanings of special interest to us.

Table 2: Selected meanings of [a]tman

Source: Monier-Williams, 1899, pp. 12 (at), 24 (an); 135 (atman) and 456 (tman),
abridged and simplified

atman (in Sanskrit script)atman, atmán, m[asculine gender].

(variously derived from an, to breathe, live; at, to move, go constantly, walk, run;
vA, to blow; cf. tmán),
the breath.

essence, nature, character, peculiarity (often at the end of a compound, e.g. karmA^tman).(variously derived from an, to breathe; at, to move; vA, to blow; cf. tmán) the breath.

the soul, principle of life and sensation.

the individual soul, self, abstract individual.

the person or whole body considered as one and opposed to the separate members of the body.

(at the end of a compound) "the understanding, intellect, mind" (cf. naSTA^tman, deprived of mind or sense, p. 532).

the highest personal principle of life, Brahma ( cf. paramA^tman) .

effort, (= dhRti), firmness.

the sun, fire.

tman, tmán m[asculine gender].

(= atmán) the vital breath.

one's own person , self; 'tman after e, or o for atman.

Copyleft  copy left  2014 W. Ulrich

Derived meanings  In addition, Apte's (1965/2008) Practical Sanskrit-English Dictionary lists the following (among other) uses of the term “atman,” all of which relate to both cognitive and emotional qualities, to the mind and the soul: "thinking faculty, the faculty of thought and reason" (p. 323); "spirit, vitality, courage" (p. 323); "mental quality" (p. 323); further, in derived and compound phrases, atman also stands for qualities or efforts such as "striving to get knowledge (as an ascetic), seeking spiritual knowledge" (p. 324); "dependent on oneself or on his own mind, self-dependence" (p. 324); "self-control, self-government" (p. 325); "knowing one's own self (family etc.), knowledge of the soul, spiritual knowledge" (p. 325); "practicing one's own duties or occupation, one's own power or ability, to the best of one's power" (p. 325); and, apparently accompanying such qualities, forms of personal conduct such as "self-purification" (p. 325), but also "self-praise" and "self-restraint" (p. 325).

Personal reading  The etymological root meaning of atman, so much is clear, refers to the activity of breathing – the vital breath – as a source of vitality that keeps us alive and moving and also allows us to grow and develop as individuals, to unfold our nature and essential character (compare the compound word jivatman, also spelled givatman, from jivá = "living, existing, alive" and tman, thus yielding "the living or personal or individual soul," cf. Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 422f, facsimile edn. only). Atman is thus also the source of our becoming what we have the potential to be spiritually and intellectually, if only we undertake the required effort of learning, by seeking to know brahman and thereby also to better know ourselves, that is, the individual self of which both our soul and our intellect are constitutive.

Müller's (1879, e.g., pp. xxx-xxxii) preferred translation of atman is indeed the "individual self" or simply the "self," meaning the essential core of a human subject that lies behind the empirical individual as it manifests itself in the phenomenal world, the aham (cf. the German ich or the Latin ego, "I"):

Beyond the aham or ego, with all its accidents and limitations, such as sex, sense, language, country, and religion, the Indian sages perceived, from a very early time, the atman or the self, independent of all such accidents. (Müller, 1879, p. xxx, added italics).

Atman, the individual self, thus distinguishes itself from both the empirical ego (aham) on the one hand and the universal or highest self (brahman) on the other hand. Atman is neither aham nor brahman; rather, it is on the way from aham to brahman, developing its contingent, empirical self towards its essential, divine self. With respect to the latter, Müller emphasizes that atman is always "a merely temporary reflex of the Eternal Self" (1879, p. xxxii; cf. his full discussion on pp. xxviii-xxxii). Atman's fundamental task is to realize itself – its individual self – in the double sense of achieving awareness (recognizing it) and growth (developing it), so that this individual self can become a fuller reflex of that higher, universal Self of which it is only an imperfect reflection.

The core topic of the Upanishads, as I understand it, is accordingly "to explain the true relation between brahman, the supreme being, and [atman,] the soul of man" (Müller, 1904/2013, p. 20). Atman's self-realization, in the double sense just explained, is gained through the effort to get to know brahman. The Upanishads therefore also refer to brahman as paramatman (or parama-atman, from paramá = most distant, highest, best, most excellent, superior, with all the heart, and tman, yielding "the supreme spirit," Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 588): paramatman is the ideal towards which jivatman, the living self, is to strive, a process of realizing one's individual nature and potential that has as its endpoint the convergence of atman with brahman, or atman's becoming atman-brahman. When this happens (in the ideal, that is), atman has found "its very self," "that [self] which should be perceived" or realized (Olivelle's apt translation of "atman" in the Mandukya Upanishad, see 1996, p. 289f, see verses 7, 8 and 12; italics added).

The distinction, and ideal convergence, of atman and brahman is also related to the fundamental notion in Hindu thought of a perpetual cycle of rebirth and transmigration of souls (samsara): atman can only free itself from samsara by moving closer to brahman, that is, by realizing its own highest self. In connection with the notion of samsara, atman's self is "the eternal core of the personality that after death either transmigrates to a new life or attains release (moksha) from the bonds of existence" (Encyclopaedia Britannica, 2013a). Which one of the two options will come true depends on the degree to which atman realizes its individual self in terms of both awareness and growth.

Atman or the search for personal growth We are, then, talking about the individual self as-it-has-the-potential-to-be rather than as-it-actually-is; about a person's vital self; about the ultimate source of its being spiritually, emotionally and intellectually alive and growing. Hamilton (2001, p. 28 and passim) similarly speaks of atman as embodying "the nature of one's essential self or soul," and Ganeri (2007, p. 3) of a "healthy self" towards which atman is to strive. Partly similar notions of personal growth are quite familiar to the Western tradition of thought. I am thinking of Carl Rogers' (1961) process of becoming and particularly of C.G. Jung's (1968b) process of individuation, a process through which a person's unconscious and conscious become one in the Self, whereby the latter concept (the Self) is understood as the archetype of psychic wholeness or totality. The difference is that in the Hindu tradition, this process reaches beyond all the limitations and contingencies of a person's life and takes on a truly cosmic dimension: the individual soul or consciousness is expected to become one with the whole universe as if individual awareness could ever include the whole of reality or, in Vedanta terms, as if atman could ever be one with brahman so as indeed to become atman-brahman.

Atman or the quest for realizing the ideal in the real  Atman's striving to become one with brahman: what a great image for the eternal tension between realism and idealism in the human quest for coming to terms with the world and, inseparable from it, for becoming (or realizing) oneself! Remarkably, in this Upanishadic image the tension can be resolved in favor of a meaningful convergence – of the human condition as it is and human development as it might be. Such convergence is conceivable in the Upanishadic framework as it sees the ultimate ground of the person (one's self-concept) in close interaction with the cosmic principles (brahman) that pervade the universe and thus also shape our awareness of the world and of ourselves. The tension between the real and the ideal is thus reconciled in the notion of a fundamental union of individual (or subjective) and universal (or objective) principles.

Kant's later attempt, in the first Critique, to explain how the human mind can grasp and understand the world at all, or in his terms, how the mind's a priori categories can be constitutive of empirical knowledge, lead him to a similar solution: the answer must be that there exists an ultimate convergence of the human mind's internal structure and principles with those of the universe (see Kant's highly differentiated analysis in the "Analytic of Principles," 1787, B169-315, esp. B193-197). The principles governing the world must be the same as those governing the human mind! For purely methodological reasons, Kant is thus compelled to postulate an ultimate unity of the cognitive conditions that account for the intelligibility of the world with the ontological conditions that account for its reality, a postulate he calls the "highest principle of all synthetic judgments" (1787, B197):

We assert that the conditions of the possibility of experience in general are likewise conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience, and that for this reason they have objective validity in a synthetic a priori judgment. (Kant, 1787, B197)

If as humans we can grasp reality at all, infinite as it is and reaching beyond our experience, it is because it is already in us, as an intrinsic part of our cognitive apparatus. In the language of the Vedanta: atman can hope at least partly to grasp the universal reality that is called "brahman" because brahman is already in atman's soul, is part of its essential nature. "The real behind empirical nature is the universal spirit within." (Mohanty, 2000, p. 2). Atmavidya (the search for understanding oneself) and brahmavidya (the search for understanding universal reality) go hand in hand.

From cultivated understanding to cultivated practice  Shifting the focus from the realm of theoretical (speculative) reason to that of practical (moral) reason, I find a similar parallelism between the deepest ideas of the traditions of Western rational ethics and ancient Indian thought. Just as Kant's "enlarged thought," the rational effort of taking into account the implications of one's subjective maxim of action for all others and thus to cultivate a sensus communis (see the earlier discussion in Ulrich, 2009b, p. 10f, and 2009d, p. 38), converges with the quest for cultivating one's moral self, so cultivated understanding of the world and individual self-cultivation also converge in the ancient Indian tradition. In Vedanta terms as well as in Buddhist terms, which in this regard do not differ, "philosophical inquiry and the practices of truth are also arts of the soul, ways of cultivating impartiality, self-control, steadiness of mind, toleration, and non-violence." (Ganeri, 2007, p. 4, added italics).

But of course, effort and achievement are not the same thing. We are talking here about an ongoing process of cultivating one's knowledge, character, and practice, rather than about an accomplishment. Despite the promise of brahman's residing in the individual, atman is only and for ever on the way to self-knowledge and self-realization. The situation resembles that of a student challenged by the teacher to never stop learning; or, in the previously quoted terms of Müller, of a pupil who is called upon to learn to know his Self rather than just himself, that is, to understand his individual self as "a merely temporary reflex of the Eternal Self" (Müller, 1879, p. xxxii). Once we realize that self-knowledge (atmavidya) is quite impossible without knowledge of that highest expression of Self called brahman (brahmavidya), and vice-versa, the challenge is unavoidable:

The highest aim of all thought and study with the Brahman of the Upanishads was to recognize his own self as a mere limited reflection of the Highest Self, to know his self in the Highest Self, and through that knowledge to return to it, and regain his identity with it. Here to know was to be, to know the Atman was to be the Atman, and the reward of that highest knowledge after death was freedom from new births, or immortality.
    That Highest Self which had become to the ancient Brahmans the goal of all their mental efforts, was looked upon at the same time as the starting-point of all phenomenal existence, the root of the world, the only thing that could truly be said to be, to be real and true. As the root of all that exists, the Atman was identified with the Brahman. (Müller, 1879, p. xxx)

Accordingly, as Müller sums up the gist of the Upanishads, the question that may guide us in reading these bewildering, mythical, partly dark and almost unintelligible, yet partly also bright and illuminating texts is this:

The question is, whether there is or whether there is not, hidden in every one of the sacred books, something that could lift up the human heart from this earth to a higher world, something that could make man feel the omnipresence of a higher Power, something that could make him shrink from evil and incline to good, something to sustain him in the short journey through life, with its bright moments of happiness, and its long hours of terrible distress. (Müller, 1879, p. xxxviii)

The human being's striving beyond the fragmentary universe within which it moves in everyday thought and practice, towards something deeper or higher, towards something that could "lift the heart up"; that's what well-understood self-knowledge (atmavidya) is all about from a Vedantic perspective. It leads us directly to the third selected idea that I find so interesting in the Upanishads' account of the general (or universal) in all human cognition and practice, the concept of jagat.

"Jagat" At first glance, it may look as if this one were the easiest of the three ideas to grasp, as the term is still used today in many regional Indian languages for referring to the experiential world in which we live. On closer inspection though, it is perhaps the most complex and interesting of the three concepts, at least from a methodological (rather than spiritual) point of view. The reason is, I believe it can make a significant difference to our competence of "enlarged thinking," or more specifically, to our understanding of the general in the particular and vice-versa and accordingly, to our skills in dealing constructively and critically with the eternal tension (or dialectic) in human thought and practice mentioned above, between the real and the ideal – the idealist and the realist sides of our grasp of reality. But let us see.

Root meanings  The Sanskrit root term contained in the second syllable of "jagat" is ga, which refers to moving, going, not too different from the English go; whence comes the Sanskrit verb gam, = to go, move, or approach; to arrive at, to accomplish or attain (see Wilson, 1819/ 2011, p. 282). The prefix ja in the first syllable means as much as "born or descended from, produced or caused by, born or produced in or at or upon, growing in, living at"; hence also "son of" or "father of," or "belonging to, connected with, peculiar to" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 407). Further, it can also mean "speedy, swift" (the only meaning given by Wilson, 1819/2011, p. 336, whereas Monier-Williams lists it almost last of the many meanings he gives) or "victorious, eaten" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 407), two meanings that point to the term's connotation of chase or hunt (Jagd in German). The prefix may also be related to the similar term ya, which among other meanings refers to that which moves or to "who goes, a goer, a mover" or also "air, wind" (Wilson, 1819/2011, p. 677, similarly Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 838). So jagat is everything that is moving or movable, undergoing variation, in flux, "especially in the sense that no fixed description of it will ever be correct" (D.P. Dash, 2013a). Here is, once again, a representative selection of meanings from the Monier-Williams Sanskrit-English Dictionary (Table 3):

Table 3: Selected meanings of jagat

Source: Monier-Williams, 1899, pp. 108 and 408, abridged and simplified

jagat (in Sanskrit script) jagat, jágat m[asculine] f[eminine] n[euter] gender.

( from gam, moving, movable, locomotive, living)

jagat, jágat m[asculine gender].

air, wind.

pl[ural use]. people , mankind.

jagat, jágat n[euter] gender.

that which moves or is alive, men and animals, animals as opposed to men, men.

the world, esp. this world, earth.

people, mankind.

the plants (or flour [ground grain] as coming from plants)

the site of a house

the world, universe

du[al number]. heaven and the lower world

pl[ural use]. the worlds (= [ja]gat-traya ["three jagats"])

jagad-atman, jagadAtman m[asculine gender].
[also
jagat-atman,e.g., Apte (1890/2014, p. 503)]

world-breath.

wind; world-soul.

the Supreme Spirit [lit. = world spirit].

Copyleft  copy left  2014 W. Ulrich

Against the background of the discussion thus far, it is interesting to note that jagat refers not only to the "world," "earth" or "universe" in general but can also take the specific meaning of "this world [of ours]" (Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 408). Jagat is the world as it manifests itself to the individual (atman) as a perceived or imagined reality, a perception that is in constant flux and does not usually capture the full, objective reality (brahman). Further, in addition to the manifest physical world, jagat may also refer specifically to "the world of the soul, [or of an individual's] body" (Apte, 1965/2008, p. 722; cf. 1890/2014, p. 503). Jagat can thus refer to different realms of the universe, such as heaven and earth. The compound nouns trijagat and jagat-traya designate the Vedantic conception of three worlds, either as "(1) the heaven, the atmosphere and the earth" or as "(2) the heaven, the earth, and the lower world" (Apte, 1965/2008. p. 789; similarly Böthlingk and Roth, 1855, p. 3-428, and Böthlingk and Schmidt, 1879/1928, p. 3-49). As a last hint, Apte also lists jagat as a grammatical object of the verbal noun nisam (lit. = not speaking, silent, observing), which refers to the act of "seeing, beholding, [having] sight [of]"; accordingly the phrase nisam jagat stands for "observing the [visible] world" and, as a result, having a certain "sight" of the world (p. 924, cf. 1890//2014, p. 638).

Derived meanings: the rich etymology of "jagat"  While the Sanskrit-English dictionaries on which I have drawn have their strength in a scholarly documentation of actual occurrences of Sanskrit terms in the ancient literature, they are less strong when it comes to explaining how old Sanskrit terms have found their way into the contemporary vocabulary of Indo-European and other languages. "Jagat" is such a term. It continues to be used in several Asian languages, including Modern Standard Hindi, in meanings related to land, earth, world, or universe, with a number of different derived connotations.21) Likewise, in the European languages (esp. in Dutch and German) one can find numerous contemporary words and entire word families that appear to be related to the ancient Sanskrit jagat. They often go back to the Old-Germanic root jag, which apparently contains the Sanskrit root terms ja and gam (as explained above) and means as much as "moving fast, chasing." Here are three examples of such word families, all of which are of particular interest to our present discussion.

(1) The German noun Jagd (= the hunt) derives directly from the Middle High German noun jaget or jagat. This etymological connection makes the combination of the two above-listed, at first glance unrelated, root meanings of the prefix ja understandable, of "speedy, swift" along with "victorious, eaten." Interestingly, the German noun originally referred not only to the activity of hunting but also to the parties involved or admitted (a meaning it still has today, although it is now rarely used in this sense), as well as to the area in which hunting was permitted. The corresponding German verb is jagen (= to hunt, figuratively also to move fast or to chase something or somebody). Similar forms exist in other North-European languages (e.g. the Dutch verb jagen, from Middle Dutch jaghen, Old Dutch jagon; likewise Swedish jaga or Swiss-German jage). The Dutch noun for Jagd is jacht (from Middle Dutch jaght), which is obviously related to the German and Dutch term for a sailing yacht, Jacht (= yacht, originally a fast moving boat or "hunting boat").

(2) The Swiss-German noun Hag (= fence, originally meaning as much as a thorn hedge that encloses a piece of land or forest) goes back to the Old High German hac and further to the Old Germanic (Proto-Germanic) hagatusjon, with many derivatives such as hagaz (= able, skilled), hag or haga (= to beat, push, thrust), and häkse (= a witch or hag, cf. Middle English hagge, from Old English haegtes; Dutch heks, German Hexe). Although the link is not definitively proven, both the form and the meaning of these and other words with the root term hag are strikingly close to jag[at]; they all connote some aspects of fast movement or hunting (e.g., chasing, stinging, hitting, capturing, fencing in). These connotations are still very apparent, for example, in the contemporary German verbs hacken (= to chop, hack; also abhacken = to chop off) and einhagen (= to hedge, to fence in), as well as in the German nouns Hecke (= a hedge, related to the Old English haga = an enclosure, a fenced-in area, and to the Middle English hawe as in hawthorn) and Gehege (= an enclosure, preserve, a fenced area of natural preservation or also an artificial habitat for animals as in the zoo).

(3) In other derivatives, the root meanings of chasing, capturing, enclosing, and delimiting take on a strong connotation of protection, as in the German verb hegen (orig. = to hedge), which now means as much as to care for, look after, cultivate, or foster (as in the phrase hegen und pflegen, to lavish care and attention on somebody or something). Figuratively used it means, for example, to nurture a hope (eine Hoffnung hegen), to entertain an expectation or a doubt (eine Erwartung hegen, einen Zweifel hegen), or to pursue an intention or plan (eine Absicht hegen, einen Plan hegen). Another derivation appears to be Hain, an old-fashioned German noun that is now chiefly used in poetic language for a grove but which originally just meant a piece of land surrounded by trees or bushes, yielding a natural delimitation for an orchard or garden, a resting place, or a small farm or other kind of dwelling. This explains why the root hag is also still frequently found today as a component in the names of plants that are characteristic of such places (e.g. Hagedorn = hawthorn, from Old English hagathorn), or Hagebutte = rose hip), as well as in many old place names (e.g., Hagen and Im obern Hag in Germany, Den Haag in the Netherlands, or Hagnau in Switzerland).

To judge from the numerous etymological sources that I have consulted, ranging from the Oxford English Dictionary to Wiktionary for English and from the Duden to the Kluge and the Wahrig dictionaries for German, it appears that the link between jagat and the first-mentioned word family around Jagd is firmly established, whereas the precise history of the modern words mentioned under points (2) and (3) lies partly in the dark. Even so, the extent to which the root meanings of these terms agree with those of the ancient Sanskrit word jagat is striking. We may sum up these root meanings as follows:

(1) the activity of movement or chase; an object that moves or undergoes change;

(2) a piece of land or site of a dwelling, or that which delimits it;

(3) an element of care, attention, interest or cultivation; this world of ours or a delimited part of it about which we care.22)

A second observation that I find striking is this. As a common denominator, all three root meanings have to do with the core notion of something bounded or limited that changes and can be changed but which is also being cared for – a core notion that I associate with my methodological interest, in my work on critical systems heuristics (CSH), in the role of boundary judgments and hence, of boundary discourse and boundary critique as tools for cultivated understanding (for an introduction see, e.g., Ulrich 1996, 2006a, 2001, and 2005). However, for the time being, let us stick to the etymology of jagat.

Personal reading  Considering the various meanings of jagat, I conclude that it may stand for virtually any object-realm of experience or awareness (and, in the case of humans, also of thought, discourse, and action) that constitutes the "world" or "universe" within which an individual's attention moves at any specific time. Characteristic of this world is that it is "moving" or changing, in the double sense that it takes on variable forms or states and thus may also be seen from multiple perspectives, so that there is no definitive description of it. Equally characteristic is that it represents a particular, partial set of the total universe of phenomena that in principle could come into sight or might be the focus of attention, and that (to use Müller's earlier-cited description of the atman's self as distinguished from the universal or higher Self) it is only a "temporary reflex" of the full reality behind the considered phenomena. Moreover, as we just observed, an active element of bounding (or boundary judgments) on the part of a human observer plays a role in each of the three word families that we have considered. The basic cognitive (logical, observational, linguistic) act involved is that of making a distinction between "within" and "without."

This active element suggests that one of the associations that go with "jagat" concerns a subject's authorship and/or ownership of it. Whatever jagat we are talking about, it is always some subject's jagat; it is the world as an individual perceives and experiences it in its current situation. In a sense, even animals – all living beings, not only humans – are authors of their jagat; we call it "habitat" (or living space) in the case of animals and "daily life world" (or realm of experience, universe of discourse, world view, etc.) in the case of people. The subject, whether an animal or a person, can to a certain extent choose, change or modify its habitat. Humans, as subjects endowed with reason, cannot avoid thinking about and questioning their perception of and situation in the world.

As a consequence of that individual authorship, but also of the infinite variety of things and aspects that make up "the world" – the total universe of things we might want to consider as parts of our individual worlds – there is an element of selection involved. We cannot usually do justice to all and every circumstance that might potentially be of interest. By implication, in talking to others we have to make it clear what parts or aspects of "the world" we are concerned or talking about; as a result of exchange with others, we may revise our individual jagat. Atman's view or conception of the world, like that of its inmost self, is always only a "temporary reflex" of the full reality. Further, due to this moving and changing character, the concept of jagat also connotes the idea of an ongoing process of change in which a subject's jagat can take on different states or stages of development and appreciation.

As I suggest to understand the term jagat, it connotes all these mentioned aspects of its being a variable object-domain; its being authored and owned by an individual; its having the selected and temporary nature of a subject's world; its being a possible object of reflection and learning, revision and development. As knowing subjects, we find ourselves in the situation of atman: we are challenged to develop not only our awareness of self – "the knowing subject within us" (Nikhilananda, 1949, p. 52) – but also that of the world around us, the world within we live, our individual jagat. We can "realize" the jagat-like nature of our world in the sense of both making ourselves aware of it and, consequently, developing it.

From an epistemological and methodological point of view, we may structure these various connotations of "jagat" a bit more systematically into three basic types of reference to the world involved in observing the world, in thinking and talking about it, and in acting in it:

(i) Jagat refers to some object(s) of cognition (the perceived) – "the world within which a subject moves," understood as a variable object-realm of perception and awareness. Characteristically, there is no definitive description of the object-domain or, to put it differently, there are no stable objects of cognition, due to the fluent and perspectival character of what can be known and said about this world of ours. Also characteristically, that which can be known or said, despite its unstable character, is of concern to some individual(s) in some context of ordinary existence and practice. Another way to describe the nature of this first type of reference to the world is by pointing to its contextual character: we perceive and talk of objects depending on the contexts in which we find ourselves or about which we care.

In the case of an animal, the jagat in question will be its natural habitat, perhaps also the larger ecosystem of which this habitat is a part. In the case of humans, a typical object domain referred to as "jagat" may originally (i.e., in the history of the term) have been a dwelling or the site of a house where people lived, or a fenced area of land where cattle was kept or crops were grown. Later on larger object domains may have moved into focus, say, a larger geographical region or a social context shared by a group of individuals or, in a more religious context, the three jagats of earth, heaven, and the lower world, and thus ultimately also the whole cosmos or any section of the real-world of interest at a specific moment. Common to any human jagat is that it is always someone's jagat and is closely related to the concerned subjects' sense of identity or "self."

(ii) Jagat refers to some subject(s) of cognition (the perceiver) "that which moves and changes" (e.g., its location, appearance, or view), understood as a bearer of knowledge and awareness, perhaps also as a source of ideas, insights and errors, as well as an agent, in its moving within the object-domain in question.23) Characteristically this subject, through its changing states of awareness as well as its changing needs and interests, is the author and owner (Sanskrit = natha or naatha, meaning "protector, patron, possessor, owner, lord," cf. Monier-Williams, 1899, p. 534, as well as "author," cf. Sanskrit and Tamil Dictionaries, 2005) of its world, the specific universe within which its perceptions, thoughts, and actions move. The object of cognition referred to under (i) above thus becomes the subject's self-created universe of discourse (or universe of thought and action), an ever-changing, self-delimited context of interest or concern within which people move as observers, speakers, or agents.

The human subject, thus conceived as observer, narrator, or agent, becomes jagannath (from jagat and natha), "the author of the considered or narrated world" – a concept that we still encounter in India today, for example, in the form of the masculine first name Jagannath as well as, in the Indian state of Odisha (formerly Orissa) and in other Indian states, as the name of a Hindu deity (a title of Krishna, the eighth avatar of Vishnu), then meaning as much as "the lord (or protector) of the universe." The term "jagannath" is also at the origin of the English loanword juggernaut, which according to my constant companion, the Complete English Oxford Dictionary, refers to an "idol of this deityJuggernaut carrying an image of Krishna (Jagannath) at Puri, Orissa, annually dragged in procession on an enormous car, under the wheels of which many devotees are said to have formerly thrown themselves to be crushed" (see the picture on the right hand; source: in the public domain, made available by the Project Gutenberg). In contemporary language it now also denotes any particularly large vehicle or machine and is synonymous with "behemoth" or "Moloch."

The double association of jagat with jagannath and juggernaut is not without its dangers. While it is apt to remind us of jagat's belonging to some author, and thus of its subjective and creative, self-authored and dynamic nature as "the moving universe within which we move," it also abets a one-sidedly religious reading (especially in popular reception). Its use in the ancient scriptures is then easily misunderstood to refer to the divine author of "that" world only (i.e., to God or some ancient Hindu deity), rather than also (and perhaps primarily) to the human authors of "this" world. Such an understanding of jagat risks obscuring its philosophical and methodological relevance, which I see in its drawing our attention to the inevitably contextual character of the world as an object of human cognition. An example is provided by the Isha Upanishad, one of the principal Upanishads associated with the Yajur Veda, which customarily is translated in such a one-sidedly religious way that the significance of its central, emphatic reference to "jagat" gets all but lost (we will discuss this example in the next essay).

(iii) Finally, by implication, jagat also refers to a state of cognition (the perception) – "the state of awareness of the world, which an unreflective subject wrongly considers as the world." Characteristically, again, there is no stable state of awareness; for awareness is always an intermediate state in an ongoing process of transformation. Jagat thus stands for a current state of consciousness and understanding in terms of which a human subject perceives and describes its world provisionally but which, as soon as we take it for granted, risks being false or arbitrary or in any case fails to capture the possible development of both the subject and the object of cognition. It is, to use Müller's (1879, p. xxxii) phrase once more, but a "temporary reflex" of the full reality that as such cannot be an object of human cognition. Which is to say, whatever we choose to say about the world is bound to be insufficient and unreliable, as is any one perspective or universe of discourse we rely upon for defining situations and acting in them. A devastating but compelling insight that is also captured in a famous Vedantic aphorism, ascribed to Adi Shankara, the major 8th/9th century commentator of the Upanishads and founder of the Advaita Vedanta school of Vedanta thought (a school of thought that emphasizes the unity of all reality and the ultimate convergence of atman and brahman):

brahman satyam, jagat mithya.
"Brahman is the real reality, the world is deceptive."
(Bowker, 2000, p. 96)

In methodological rather than metaphysical terms, we might put it this way: "One perceives the reality of one's own world," and "one thinks the thoughts of one's own universe of thought." The good news is that we can choose to heed this admonishment ¬ the Upanishadic way of developing our skills as knowing and acting subjects.

Concluding comment  We are reaching the end of this introductory analysis of the three selected Upanishadic ideas, brahman, atman, and jagat. Is there any concise way to sum it up? If so, perhaps the most noteworthy finding consists in the rather striking parallels that we have encountered between these Upanisadic ideas and the "Western" ideas of reason that Kant examined most profoundly in his critique of reason, ideas that remain indispensable today with a view to ensuring to reason what may be its three most basic virtues: unity of thought, morality of action, and rationality of argumentation.24) The parallels in question include:

(a) the general character of these ideas: they guide us beyond the limits of the apparently given, empirical world; due to their decontextualizing thrust, they compel us to recognize and question the self-constructed limitations of our perceptions of the world and of our related universes of discourse and action;

(b) their unavoidable but simultaneously problematic character: reason cannot do without them, but at the same time it cannot demonstrate that they have any objective validity and thus it also cannot rely on them for validating the generalizations they suggest to us;

(c) their unconditional character: they refer us to the notion of an unconditioned totality (or a complete series) of conditions, a notion that is implied in all sufficient explanation or understanding of things yet exceeds the limits of possible knowledge; which is to say, all these ideas confront us with the limitations of human knowledge and reason;

(d) their character as limiting concepts: they embody projected endpoints of thought that we need for systematic thinking, although we can only approximate but never reach these endpoints;

(e) their confronting us with a fundamental tension between the demands of reason and what it can achieve in reality: they remind us of the perennial clash of idealism and realism in human thought and practice;

(f) their anticipated convergence of the real (empirical) and the ideal (universal) in the constitution of human knowledge: inquiry into the nature of the world cannot avoid postulating that the ontological conditions that account for its reality and the cognitive conditions that account for its intelligibility coincide;

(g) and finally, their doubly challenging character with a view to critical inquiry and practice: reason needs to learn to employ them for critical purposes while at the same time handling them critically, that is, refraining from any positive validity claims based on their use.

In view of these shared characteristics, I propose that from a methodological point of view, both the Upanishadic and the Kantian ideas are probably best understood as ideas that lend themselves to merely critical employment. They do not warrant any kinds of generalizing claims about the world. Borrowing an apt phrase of Ryle (1949, pp. 117 and 122; 2009, pp. 105 and 110f), we might say that ideas of reason represent no inference-tickets (or licences) for claiming knowledge and rationality beyond the limits of contextual assumptions. Rather, they challenge us to deal carefully with such assumptions. This is possible inasmuch as contextual assumptions, although unavoidable, are variable. We can try to change them so as to do justice to a situation; we can share and discuss them with others; and we can carefully qualify and limit the claims that depend on them.

General ideas of reason, meaning both Upanishadic and Kantian ideas, are in this respect similar to ideals: although human inquiry and practice will never completely "realize" their intent, that is, understand it and make it real, we can at least try to approximate it and to do justice to it partly, in some well-reasoned ways. Their counter-factual nature then does not make ideas of reason useless, no more than ideals. Quite the contrary, it creates a healthy distance to "normal" knowledge and practice and in this way provides impetus for approximating their intent in ways that are critically reflected, systematic, and arguable. This is precisely the kind of use that we had in mind in a previous essay of this series (see Ulrich, 2014b), where we explored the "approximation" of general ideas by means of what we initially described as a "double movement of critical thought" and then came to understand as a "cycle of critical contextualization," that is, a process of systematic clarification of contextual assumptions by means of iterative decontextualization (or universalization) and (re-)contextualization (or specification) of the assumptions and implications of claims.

At the end of this examination of the notions of brahman, atman, and jagat, we can thus note that we have encountered similar intentions as well as similar limitations among Upanishadic and Kantian ideas. From a methodological rather than metaphysical or religious perspective, none of these ideas is adequately understood if we take them to guide us towards secure knowledge and rational practice. Neither certainty of knowledge nor a guarantee of rational practice is within their reach. They nevertheless retain an indispensable role for reason, in that they offer us a deeper understanding of the limitations of human knowledge, thought, and practice and thus can also guide us in dealing systematically with these limitations. There is a deep affinity between Upanishadic and Kantian ideas in this respect: they touch upon ultimate limitations and challenges of the human quest for understanding the world we live in and for improving our lives. Therein I locate their shared, lasting relevance for our epoch, and therein I also see the reason why they continue to fascinate so many people world-wide.

In the continuation of this exploration, in two subsequent Bimonthlies, we will first illustrate the analysis made thus far by applying it to a major Upanishadic text, and subsequently will situate the understanding gained of the three core concepts of brahman, atman and jagat within our developing framework of critical pragmatism. As this is the last Bimonthly essay of the year, I take the opportunity to thank you for visiting my site and to wish you and your families a happy end of the year.

(To be continued)

 

Previous |

 Next

For a hyperlinked overview of all issues of "Ulrich's Bimonthly" and the previous "Picture of the Month" series, see the site map

PDF file

Note: This is the fifth essay on the role of general ideas in rational thought and action. It continuous the exploration of the world of ideas of the ancient Indian Upanishads with an analysis of three essential concepts selected from them, brahman, atman, and jagat. The previous essays of the series appeared in the Bimonthlies of September-October 2013, January-February 2014, July-August 2014, and .September-October 2014.

 

Notes

20) The proper use of reason entails a double challenge to reason. On the one hand, reason itself is the only instance to control its proper use; on the other hand, it has to become practical, that is, it must "work" (ensure proper results) in real-world practice. Compare on this double touchstone Kant's (1787) call, in the preface of the first Critique, for a self-tribunal of reason along with Ganeri's (2001) nicely complementary call, in the subtitle of his book on classical Indian philosophy, for the proper work of reason. I have deliberately chosen the phrase "proper use of reason" so as to remind us of both touchstones of reason: when it comes to ensuring a proper use of reason, "proper" means "self-critical" (reason's concern in its own integrity) as well as "effective" (reason as a critical instance of practice). Bringing these two concerns together is the essence of what I propose we understand by reflective practice.  [BACK]

21) The word "jagat" or derivatives of it can be found today in several languages of India that belong to the Indo-European language family (e.g., Modern Standard Hindi, Bengali, and Odia or formerly Oriya) as well as in others, for example in Tamil, which belongs to the Dravinian language family and knows the Sanskrit loan word "jagat" as well as its variant "jakat" for "world"). It is also found in other contemporary languages of South-East Asia, for example, in Malay and Indonesian, which belong to the Austronesian language family, and in Indo-German languages spoken in and outside India such as Nepali, the lingua franca of Nepal, and Modern Standard Urdu, a variant of Hindi that is the lingua franca of Pakistan and North India and is rather similar to Hindi but is writtten in Urdu script rather than Devanagari. In these contemporary languages, "jagat" now basically means as much as "land," "world," or "universe." For example, as the Hindi-English Online Dictionary tells me, "Academia" (the academic world) is referred to in contemporary Hindi as "shiksha-jagat," meaning literally "the world of education"; the same phrase occurs in Odia. Further, as my appreciated colleague of Indian origin and co-editor of the Journal of Research Practice, D.P. Dash (2013d) informs me, there exist today in India a few news media such as Jagat Kranti, a Hindi newspaper with currently neglible online presence; Samachar Jagat, an electronic newspaper that comes mostly in Devanagari script; and Jagat News, a news aggregation website that currently is under reconstruction. In Jakarta, Indonesia, I find Jagat Review, an online service offering reviews of household electronics, games, movies, etc. (By the way, the name of the city of Jakarta, too, is etymologically related to jagat.) The term also appears as part of the names of cinemas (e.g., Jagat Cinema in Old Dehli), gaming sites (e.g., Jagat Play), hotels (e.g., Jagat Palace), and so on. It is quite possible that the term "jagat" is used more widely today than in the epoch in which the Upanishads originated (approximately 800-500 BCE). For readers who would like to do their own research, a good scholarly source to begin with is the Digital Libraries of South Asia site (CLR, 2013).  [BACK]

22) Many more examples can be found of contemporary English and German words that (with varying degrees of plausibility and available evidence) appear to be related to the three word families and which thus may also have some roots in jagat. Examples in English are the words to act, active, actor, agent, agile, chase, haw, jacket, jag, jagged, jaguar, to jog, to joggle; and jug; and in German, the words achten (= to esteem, respect), ächten (= to ostracize, banish), beachten (= to pay attention to, take into account), beobachten (= to observe), agieren, agil, Acker (=acre, field), Agrar-, Agrikultur, Aktie (= share), aushecken (= to hatch, think up), behaglich (= comfortable, cosy), hager (=haggard, lean, scraggy), Heck (=orig. gate in a hag, opening in a hedge, now back or rear door of a vehicle), Jacke (=jacket, from Middle English jaket and related to Old French jaque), joggen (= to jog), and many others.  [BACK]

23) Interestingly, and conforming to this reading of jagat, the Swedish language knows the words jag for "I" and, derived from it, jaget for "selfhood" (ipseity), that is, all the characteristics or conditions that make up a person's sense of identity and which may also result in a state of self-centeredness or selfishness. Compare, for example, the Swedish title of Erwin Goffman's (1959) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, "Jaget och maskerna," which literally means as much as "self and masks," amounting to a title such as "The Self and its Masks" or (including the Swedish edition's subtitle) "Sense of Identity and Use of Masks in Presenting Oneself" (see Goffmann, 1974; thanks are due to D.P. Dash, 2014c, for drawing my attention to the Swedish book title).  [BACK]

24) Compare on these three basic virtues (or demands) of reason the corresponding critically-heuristic ideas (or quasi-transcendental ideas) in my work on CSH, by which I mean ideas that play an essential part in "securing at least as critical solution to the problem of practical reason" – the systems idea, the moral idea, and the guarantor idea (Ulrich, 1983; on the concept of a "critical solution," see pp. 20, 35-37, 176f, 198, 265f, 313, and on the concept of "critically-heuristic ideas," pp. 231-234, 239f, 257-264).  [BACK]

 

 

References (cumulative)

Apte, V.S. (1890/2014). The Apte 1890 Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Based on the Apte Sanskrit-English / English-Sanskrit Dictionary, 3rd. edn. Poona: Prasad Prakashan, 1920. Searchable online edition by the Cologne Project, Institute of Indology and Tamil Studies, University of Cologne, Germany, 2014 edition.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/AP90Scan/2014/web/index.php

Apte, V.S. (1920/2014). Apte English-Sanskrit Dictionary. Based on the Apte Sanskrit-English / English-Sanskrit Dictionary, 3rd. edn. Poona: Prasad Prakashan, 1920. Searchable online edition by the Cologne Project, Institute of Indology and Tamil Studies, University of Cologne, Germany, 2014 edition.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/AEScan/2014/web/index.php

Apte, V.S. (1965/2008). The Practical Sanskrit-English Dictionary. 3 vols., Poona, India: Prasad Prakashan, 1957-1959. 4th, rev. and enlarged edn., Delhli, India: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1965. Online version, last updated in June 2008.
[HTML]
http://dsal1.uchicago.edu/dictionaries/apte/
[HTML]
https://archive.org/stream/practicalsanskri00apteuoft#page/n5/mode/2up
(facsimile of 1965 edn.)

Arendt, H. (1958). The Human Condition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Aristotle (1985). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated, with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary, by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

Aurobindo, S. (1996). The Upanishads: Texts, Translations and Commentaries. Twin Lakes, WI: Lotus Light Publications (orig. 1914;1st US edn.).
[PDF]
http://www.aurobindo.ru/workings/sa/12/isha_e.pdf (transl. of Isha Upanishad)

Baier, K. (1958). The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Abridged edn., New York: Random House, 1965.

Beck, U. (1992). Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage.

Beck, U. (1995). Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

Bok, S. (1993). Foreword. In M. Gandhi (1957); An Autobiography: The Story of my Experiments With Truth, Boston, MA: Beacon Press (reprint edn. of the orig. 1957 edn.,with this new foreword). Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp. xiii-xviii.

Böthlingk, O., and Roth, R. (1855). Sanskrit-Wörterbuch. Herausgegeben von der Kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Sanskrit-German Dictionary. So-called Grosses Petersburger Wörterbuch [Greater St. Petersburg Dictionary, 7 vols.]. St. Petersburg, Russia: Kaiserliche Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1855-1875.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/PWGScan/disp2/index.php
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/pwgindex.html ( facsimile reprint edn)

Böthlingk, O., and Schmidt, R. (1879/1928). Sanskrit-Wörterbuch in kürzerer Fassung. Herausgegeben von der Kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Sanskrit-German Dictionary. So-called Kleines Petersburger Wörterbuch [Smaller St. Petersburg Dictionary]. St. Petersburg, Russia: Kaiserliche Akademie der Wissenschaften, two parts, 1879-1889, mit Nachträgen von R. Schmidt, 1928.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/PWScan/disp2/index.php
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/pwindex.html
[HTML]
https://archive.org/stream/sanskritwrterb01bhuoft#page/n3/mode/2up (facsimile of Part 1, 1879 edn.)

Bowker, J. (ed.) (2000). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of World Religions. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
[HTML]
http://www.encyclopedia.com/doc/1O101-Brahmansatyamjagatmithya.html

Carnap, R. (1928). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Leipzig, Germany: Felix Meiner Verlag. English transl. by R.A. George: The Logical Structure of the World: Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, University of California Press, 1967 (new edn. Chicago, IL: Open Court, 2003).

Cologne Project (1997/2008). Monier-Williams Sanskrit-English Dictionary (2008 revision). Institute of Indology and Tamil Studies, Cologne Sanskrit Dictionary Project. Cologne University, Köln, Germany, orig. 1997, rev. edn. 2008.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/monier/

Cologne Project (2013/14). Cologne Digital Sanskrit Dictionaries. Access page to all the Sanskrit lexicons prepared by the Institute of Indology and Tamil Studies, Cologne University, as of October 2014 (in progress).
[HTML] http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/ (2014 version, last updated Oct 1, 2014)
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/index_prev.html (2013 version, last updated June 21, 2014)

CRL (2013). Digital Dictionaries of South Asia. Digital South Asia Library (DSAL), A Program of the Center for Research Libraries (CRL) and the University of Chicago.
[HTML] http://dsal.uchicago.edu/dictionaries

Dash, D.P. (2013a). Personal email communication, 25 October.

Dash, D.P. (2013d). Personal email communication, 29 October.

Dash, D.P. (2014a). Personal email communication, 29 September.

Dash, D.P. (2014b). Personal communication, 6 October.

Dash, D.P. (2014c). Personal email communication, 29 November.

Dash, J. (2011). In quest of excellence: the problem of predication. Acarya Sankara's analysis of the Gita. Indian Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 5, No. 1, pp. 113-128.

Dewey, J. (1930). The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action. London: George Allen & Unwin. (Orig. Gifford Lectures delivered at the University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, Scotland, 1929; republished by Capricorn Books, Oakville, Ontario, Canada, 1960).

Easwaran, E. (2007). The Upanishads, Introduced and Translated by Eknath Easwaran; Afterword by Michael N. Nagler [with short introductions to each Upanishad by M.N. Nagler]. 2nd edn. Berkeley, CA /Tomales, CA: Blue Mountain Center of Meditation /Nilgiri Press (1st edn. 1987).

Encyclopaedia Britannica (2013a). Entry "Atman." Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
[HTML]
http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/41350/atman

Encyclopaedia Britannica (2013b). Entry "Brahman." Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
[HTML]
http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/77039/brahman

Encyclopaedia Britannica (2013c). Entry "Hinduism." Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
[HTML]
http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/266312/Hinduism

Encyclopaedia Britannica (2013d). Entry "Panini." Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
[HTML] http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/441324/Panini

Gandhi, M. (1957). An Autobiography: The Story of my Experiments With Truth. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Pb. reprint edn. with a new foreword by S. Bok, 1993. (Note: there exist various editions from different publishers, the 1957 edn. is the original American edn.)

Ganeri, J. (1999). Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1999.

Ganeri, J. (2001). Philosophy in Classical India: The Proper Work of Reason. London and New York: Routledge (also Dehli: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 2006, pocket book edn. 2009).

Ganeri, J. (2007). The Concealed Art of the Soul: Theories of the Self and Practices of Truth in Indian Ethics and Epistemology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Goffman, E. (1959). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. New York: Anchor Books / Doubleday.

Goffman, E. (1974). Jaget och maskerna: En studie i vardagslivets dramatik.. Stockholm, Sweden: Rabén & Sjögren.

Habermas, J. (1975). Legitimation Crisis. Boston, MA: Beacon Press (German orig. Legitimationsprobleme im Spätkapitalismus, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1973).

Habermas, J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press (German orig. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, 2 vols. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1981).

Habermas, J. (1990a). The new obscurity: the crisis of the welfare state and the exhaustion of utopian energies. In J. Habermas, The New Conservatism: Cultural Criticism and the Historian's Debate. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press (also Boston, MA: MIT Press; German orig. Die Neue Unübersichtlichkeit, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1985).

Habermas, J. (1990b). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press (German orig.: Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983).

Habermas, J. (1990c). Discourse ethics: notes on a program of philosophical justification. In J. Habermas (1990). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, pp. 43-115.

Habermas, J. (1993). Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics.

Habermas, J. (1998). The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, J. (2009). Philosophische Texte. 5 vols. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp. Vol. 2: Rationalitäts- und Sprachtheorie.

Hamilton, S. (2001). Indian Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. (Very Short Introductions.) Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press (orig. 2000).

Hare, R.M. (1981). Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press /Clarendon Press.

Hindi-English Dictionary (no ed., n.d.). Hindi to English and English to Hindi Online Dictionary and Transliteration. Allows transliteration of Hindi terms from Devanagari to Roman letters. 
[HTML]
http://hindi-english.org/

Hume, R.E. (1996). The Thirteen Principal Upanishads. Translated from the Sanskrit with an Outline of the Philosophy of the Upanishads and an Annotated Bibliography, 2nd edn. London: Oxford University Press (orig. 1921).
[HTML]
https://archive.org/details/thirteenprincipa028442mbp (facsimile of 1921 edn.)

Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Illich, I. (1971). Deschooling Society. New York: Harper & Row.

Illich, I. (1975). Medical Nemesis: The Expropriation of Health. London: Calder & Boyars. Pocket book edn. New York: Random House /Bantam Books, 1976.

James, W. (1907). Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. Longman Green & Co: New York.

Jung, C.G. (1966). Two Essays in Analytical Psychology. The Collected Works of C.G. Jung, Vol. 7. New York: Bollingen Foundation / Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

Jung, C.G. (1968a). The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious. The Collected Works of C.G. Jung, Vol. 9, Part I. 2nd edn. New York: Bollingen Foundation / Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

Jung, C.G. (1968b). A study in the process of individuation. In Jung, C.G. (1968a), The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious. The Collected Works of C.G. Jung, Vol. 9, Part I. 2nd edn. New York: Bollingen Foundation / Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 290-354.

Kant, I. (1786). Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. 2nd edn. [B] (1st edn. [A] 1785). Transl. by H.J. Paton. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1964. German orig.: Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, 1st edn. [A] and 2nd edn. [B], in: W. Weischedel (ed.), Werkausgabe Vol. VII, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1977 (orig. 1968), pp. 9-102.

Kant, I. (1787). Critique of Pure Reason. 2nd edn. [B] (1st edn. [A] 1781). Transl. by N.K. Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965 (orig. Macmillan, New York, 1929). German orig.: Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 1st edn. [A] 1781, 2nd edn. [B] 1787, in: W. Weischedel (ed.), Werkausgabe Vols. III and IV, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp 1977 (orig. 1968).

Kant, I. (1788). Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy. Transl. by L.W. Beck. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1949. German orig.: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, 1st ed. [A], in: W. Weischedel (ed.), Werkausgabe Vol. VII, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1977 (orig. 1968), pp. 105-320.

Kant I. (1793). Critique of Judgment. 2nd ed. [B] (1st ed. [A] 1790). Transl. by T.H. Bernard. New York: Hafner, 1951. German orig.: Kritik der Urteilskraft, in: W. Weischedel (ed.), Werkausgabe Vol. X, Kritik der Urteilskraft, Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp, 1977.

King, R. (1999). Indian Philosophy: An Introduction to Hindu and Buddhist Thought. Edinburgh, Scotland: Edinburgh University Press.

Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 1: The Philosophy of Moral Development – Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

Macdonell, A.A. (1929). A Practical Sanskrit Dictionary. With Transliteration, Accentuation, and Etymological Analysis Throughout. London: Oxford University Press, 1929 (= facsimile reprint edn. of A Practical Sanskrit Dictionary, London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1893).
[HTML]
http://dsal.uchicago.edu/dictionaries/macdonell/ (digitized version)
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/MDScan/2014/web/index.php

Mead, G.H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Ed. by C.W. Morris. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Menand, L. (2001). The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

Mohanty, J.N. (2000). Classical Indian Philosophy. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Monier-Williams, M. (1872). A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Rev. edn. 1899. (Note; the standard edn. now used is the 1899 edn., cited below and in the text as Monier-Williams, M. (1899.)
[HTML] 
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/MW72Scan/2014/web/index.php 

Monier-Williams, M. (1877). Hinduism. (Series Non-Christian Religious Systems). London: Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge, and New York: Pott, Young & Co. (also E. & J.B. Young, 1885; facsimile reprint edn., Charleston, SC: BiblioLife Reproduction Series, 2009, and Hong Kong: Forgotten Books, 2013).
[HTML]
https://archive.org/details/hinduism00wilgoog (facsimile edn. of 1877/2013)

Monier-Williams, M. (1891). Brahmanism and Hinduism; or, Religious Thought and Life in India, as Based on the Veda and Other Sacred Books of the Hindus. 4th edn., enlarged and improved edn. London: John Murray. (Various facsimile reprint editions, e.g. Boston, MA: Delaware/Adamant Eilibron Classics, 2005, and online editions, e.g. Hong Kong: Forgotten Books, 2012).
[HTML]
https://archive.org/details/brahmanismhindui00moni (facsimile of 1891 edn.)

Monier-Williams, M. (1899). A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Etymologically and Philologically Arranged, with Special Reference to Cognate Indo-European Languages, rev. edn., Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Orig. edn. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 1872; reprint edn., Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press /Clarendon Press, 1951; "Greatly enlarged and improved edn.," Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1960, and Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1995).
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/MWScan/2014/web/index.php (2014 edn.)
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/monier/indexcaller.php (2013 edn.)
[HTML] https://archive.org/stream/sanskritenglishd00moniuoft#page/n3/mode/2up (facsimile of enlarged 1960 edn.)
[HTML]
http://lexica.indica-et-buddhica.org/dict/lexica (online search tool)
(Note: Compare the entries "Cologne Project, 1997/2008" and 2013/14, as well as "Monier-Williams et al., 2008" in this list of references).  

Monier-Williams, M., Cappeller, C., Leumann, E., Malten, T., Mahoney, R. (2008). Monier-Williams Sanskrit-English Dictionary, HTML Version. Conversion to HTML from Cologne source version by R. Mahoney. Oxford, North Canterbury, New Zealand: Indica et Buddhica.
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/mwquery/ (2008 advanced search)
[HTML] http://lexica.indica-et-buddhica.org/dict/lexica (source version, searchable)
[HTML]
http://indica-et-buddhica.org/repositorium/dictionaries (downloadable versions, restricted access)

Müller, F.M. (1879) The Upanishads. Translated by F. Max Müller, in two parts, Part I (Vol. 1 of The Sacred Books of the East, Translated by Various Oriental Scholars and Edited by F. Max Müller). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
[HTML]
https://archive.org/stream/upanishads01ml#page/n7/mode/2up (facsimile edn.)
[HTML]
http://www.sacred-texts.com/hin/sbe01/index.htm (e-book version)

Müller, F.M. (1884) The Upanishads. Translated by F. Max Müller, in two parts, Part 2 (Vol. 15 of The Sacred Books of the East, Translated by Various Oriental Scholars and Edited by F. Max Müller). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
[HTML]
https://archive.org/stream/p2upanishads00mluoft#page/n7/mode/2up (facsimile edn.)
[HTML]
http://www.sacred-texts.com/hin/sbe15/index.htm (e-book version)

Müller, F.M. (1904/2013). Three Lectures on the Vedanta Philosophy, Delivered at the Royal Institution in March, 1894. London: Longman, Green & Co., 1904. Facsimile reprint edition, Hong Kong: Forgotten Books, 2013.
[HTML] http://www.forgottenbooks.org/readbook/Three_Lectures_on_the_Vedanta_Philosophy_1000175359 (facsimile edn.)

Müller, F.M., and Navlakha, S. (2000). The Thirteen Principal Upanishads. Transl. by F.M. Müller (1879 and 1884), rev. and ed. by S. Navlakha. Ware, Hertfordshire, UK: Wordsworth Editions.

Nagler, M.N. (2006). The constructive programme. In: R.L. Johnson (ed.), Gandhi's Experiments with Truth: Essential Writings by and about Mahatma Gandhi. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 253-262.

Nagler, M.N. (2007). Afterword: A religion for modern times. In E. Easwaran (2007). The Upanishads, Introduced and Translated by Eknath Easwaran. Berkeley, CA /Tomales, CA: Blue Mountain Center of Meditation /Nilgiri Press (2nd edn., orig. 1987), pp. 295-336.

Navlakha, S. (2000). Introduction. In: Müller, F.M., and Navlakha, S. (2000), The Thirteen Principal Upanishads. Transl. by F.M. Müller, rev. and ed. by S. Navlakha. Ware, Hertfordshire, UK:Wordsworth Edtions, pp. ix-xxxi.

Nikhilananda, Swami (1949). The Upanishads, Translated from the Sanskrit with Introductions, Vol. 1: Katha, Isha, Kena, and Mundaka. New York: Harper & Brothers.
[PDF] http://www.estudantedavedanta.net/Swami%20Nikhilananda...

Nikhilananda, Swami (1952). The Upanishads, Translated from the Sanskrit with Introductions, Vol. 2: Shvetashvatara, Prashna, and Mandukya with Gaudapada's Karika. New York: Harper & Brothers.
[PDF] http://www.estudantedavedanta.net/swami%20nikhilananda...

Nikhilananda, Swami (1956). The Upanishads, Translated from the Sanskrit with Introductions, Vol. 3: Aitareya and Brihadaranyaka. New York: Harper & Brothers.
[PDF] http://www.estudantedavedanta.net/swami%20nikhilananda...

Nikhilananda, Swami (1959). The Upanishads, Translated from the Sanskrit with Introductions, Vol. 4: Taittyria and Chhandogya. New York: Harper & Brothers.
[PDF] http://www.estudantedavedanta.net/Swami%20Nikhilananda...

Nikhilananda, Swami (2003). The Principal Upanishads. Mineola, NY¨: Dover Publications (orig. London: George Allen & Unwin, and New York: Bell, 1963, an abridged edn. of the orig. four-volume edn., New York: Harper & Brothers, 1949ff).

Nobel Committee (2006): The Nobel Prize in Physics 2006, Press Release. Stockholm: The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, 3 October 2006,
http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/2006/press.html

Olivelle, P. (1996). Upanisads. Translated from the Original Sanskrit. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press / Oxford World's Classics.

Panini (1977). The Ashtadhyayi of Panini. Edited and translated into English by S.C. Vasu (2 vols.). Dehli: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers.

Peirce, C.S. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. Popular Science Monthly, 12, January, pp. 286-302. Reprinted in C. Hartshorneand P. Weiss (eds) (1934), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. V: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism, Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, para. 5.388-5.410.

Phillips, S.H. (1996). Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of New Logic. Chicago, IL: Open Court.; improved Indian edn., Dehli: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1997.

Phillips, S.H. (2011)., Epistemology in classical Indian philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2011 Edition. E.N. Zalta (ed.)..
[HTML] http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/epistemology-india/
[PDF] https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/preview/epistemology-india/

Phillips, S.H. (2012). Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy: The Knowedge Sources of the Nyaya School. New York: Routledge.

Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Polanyi, M. (1966). The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

Popper, K.R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson. New ed. London: Routledge 2002 (German orig. 1935).

Popper, K.R. (1968). Epistemology without a knowing subject. In B. van Rootselaar and J.F. Staal (eds.), Proceedings of the Third International Congress for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, 25 Aug. to 2 Sept. 1967, Amsterdam, pp. 333–373: reprinted in Popper (1972), pp. 106-152.

Popper, K.R. (1972). Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Prabhavananda, Swami, and Manchester, F. (1984). The Upanishads: Breath of the Eternal. New York: Penguin/Signet Classics (orig. Hollywood, CA: The Vedanta Society of Sourthern California, 1948).

Prince, G.M. (1970). The Practice of Creativity: A Manual for Dynamic Group Problem Solving. New York: Harper & Row.

Puligandla, R. (1997). Fundamentals of Indian Philosophy. New Delhi: D.K. Printworld Ltd. (orig. Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1975).

Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Rogers, C.R. (1961). On Becoming a Person: A Therapist's View of Psychotherapy. New York: Houghton Mifflin.

Rudner, R.S. (1966). Philosophy of Social Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson's University Library. Reprint edn. (facsimile), with a new introduction by D.C. Dennet, London: Penguin, 2000. Also available as 60th Anniversary edn., with a critical essay by J. Tanney, Abingdon, UK: Routledge, 2009 (different pagination).

Sanskrit and Tamil Dictionaries (2005). [Part of the Cologne Project (2013/14)].
[HTML]
http://www.sanskrit-lexicon.uni-koeln.de/scans/MWScan/tamil/index.html

Sanskrit Dictionary (no ed., n.d.). Entry "Jagat." Sanskrit Online Dictionary,
[HTML]
http://sanskritdictionary.org/jagat

Schlick, M. (1918). Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Springer (2nd edn. 1925). English transl. by A.E. Blumberg: General Theory of Knowledge, Chicago, IL: Open Court, 1985.

Schön, D. (1983). The Reflective Practitioner: How Professionals Think in Action. New York: Basic Books. Paperback edn. Aldershot, UK: Arena/Ashgate Publishing, 1995.

Schön, D. (1987). Educating the Reflective Practitioner: Towards A New Design for Teaching and Learning in the Professions. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

Sharma, C. (2000). A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy. Dehli: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers (orig. London: Hutchinson/ Rider & Co., 1960; in addition, an U.S. American version was published under the title Indian Philosophy: A Critical Survey, New York: Barnes & Noble, 1962).

Simon, H. (1957). Models of Man. New York: Wiley.

SpokenSanskrit.de (n.d.). Sanskrit to English and English to Sanskrit online Dictionary and Transliteration. Allows transliteration of Sanskrit terms from Roman to Devanagari letters.
[HTML]
www.spokensanskrit.de/

Swami J[naneshvara Bharati] (n.d.). Purna: The Full, Infinite, Whole, Complete –From the Isha Upanishad. Traditional Yoga and Meditation of the Himalayan Masters.
[HTML]
http://www.swamij.com/upanishad-isha-purna.htm

Tamilcube.com (n.d.). English to Sanskrit Translation, and Converter Tool To Type in Sanskrit. Allows transliteration of Sanskrit terms from Devanagari to Roman letters.
[HTML] http://tamilcube.com/sanskrit/

Toulmin, S.E. (2003). The Uses of Argument. Updated edition. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (orig. 1958).

Tugendhat, E. (1993). Vorlesungen über Ethik. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp.

Ulrich, W. (1975). Kreativitätsförderung in der Unternehmung: Ansatzpunkte eines Gesamtkonzepts. Bern, Switzerland, and Stuttgart, Germany: Paul Haupt.

Ulrich, W. (1983). Critical Heuristics of Social Planning: A New Approach to Practical Philosophy. Bern, Switzerland: Haupt. Pb. reprint edn. Chichester, UK; and New York: Wiley, 1994.

Ulrich, W. (1993). Some difficulties of ecological thinking, considered from a critical systems perspective: a plea for critical holism. Systems Practice, 6, No. 6, pp. 583-611.

Ulrich, W. (1996). A Primer to Critical Systems Heuristics for Action Researchers. Hull, UK: University of Hull Centre for Systems Studies. .
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_1996a.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2000). Reflective practice in the civil society: the contribution of critically systemic thinking. Reflective Practice, 1, No. 2, pp. 247-268.

Ulrich, W. (2001). The quest for competence in systemic research and practice. Systems Research and Behavioral Science, 18, No. 1, pp. 3-28.

Ulrich, W. (2005). Can nature teach us good research practice? A critical look at Frederic Vester’s bio-cybernetic systems approach (book review). Journal of Research Practice, 1, No. 1, 2005, article R2. Updated and extended version: The art of interconnected thinking: Frederic Vester's biocybernetic systems approach, 21 Oct 2015.
[HTML] 
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/1/2 (orig. version)
[PDF] http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/1/1 (orig. version)
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/ulrich_2015f (rev. 2015 version)

Ulrich, W. (2006a). The art of boundary crossing: another introduction to boundary critique. Ulrich's Bimonthly, May 2006.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/picture_may2006.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/picture_may2006.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2006b). Critical pragmatism: a new approach to professional and business ethics. In L. Zsolnai (ed.), Interdisciplinary Yearbook of Business Ethics, Vol. I, Oxford, UK, and Bern, Switzerland: Peter Lang Academic Publishers, 2006, pp. 53-85.

Ulrich, W. (2006c). A plea for critical pragmatism. (Reflections on critical pragmatism, Part 1). Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2006.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2006.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2006.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2006d). Rethinking critically reflective research practice: beyond Popper's critical rationalism. Journal of Research Practice, 2, No. 2, article P1.
[HTML]
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/view/64/63)
[PDF]
http://jrp.icaap.org/index.php/jrp/article/download/64/120

Ulrich, W. (2007a). Theory and practice II: the rise and fall of the "primacy of theory." (Reflections on critical pragmatism, Part 3). Ulrich's Bimonthly, January-February 2007.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_january2007.html
[PDF] http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_january2007.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2008a). Reflections on reflective practice (1/7): The mainstream concept of reflective practice and its blind spot. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2008 (1 March 2008).
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2008.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2008.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2008b). Reflections on reflective practice (3/7): In search of practical reason. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2008 (8 Sep 2008).
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2008.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2008.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2008c). Practical reason: "Drawing the future into the present." Ulrich's Bimonthly, November-December 2008.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_november2008.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_november2008.pdf  

Ulrich, W. (2009a). Reflections on reflective practice (4/7): Philosophy of practice and Aristotelian virtue ethics. Ulrich's Bimonthly, January-February 2009.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_january2009.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_january2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2009b). Reflections on reflective practice (5/7): Practical reason and rational ethics: Kant. Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2009.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_march2009.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2009c). Reflections on reflective practice (6a/7): Communicative rationality and formal pragmatics – Habermas 1. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2009.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2009.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2009d). Reflections on reflective practice (6b/7): Argumentation theory and practical discourse – Habermas 2. Ulrich's Bimonthly, November-December 2009.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich/bimonthly_november2009.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich/downloads/bimonthly_november2009.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2010a). Exploring discourse ethics (1/2). Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2010.
[HTML]
http://wulrich/bimonthly_march2010.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich/downloads/bimonthly_march2010.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2010b). Exploring discourse ethics (2/2). Ulrich's Bimonthly, May-June 2010.
[HTML]
http://wulrich/bimonthly_may2010.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich/downloads/bimonthly_may2010.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2011a). What is good professional practice? (Part 1: Introduction).
Ulrich's Bimonthly, March-April 2011.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich/bimonthly_march2011.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_march2011.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2011b) Kant's rational ethics. Review of I. Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, transl. by H.J. Paton, New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1964. Amazon Customer Review, 7 July 2011.
[HTML]
 Amazon_review_R3QF7O0M22FFS8_Kant_Groundwork

Ulrich, W. (2011c). A note on the convergence of Kant's concepts of rationality, morality, and politics. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2011.
[HTML] http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2011.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2011.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2012a). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 1: OR as applied systems thinking. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 63, No. 9 (September), pp. 1228-1247.

Ulrich, W. (2012b). Operational research and critical systems thinking – an integrated perspective. Part 2: OR as argumentative practice. Journal of the Operational Research Society, 63, No. 9 (September), pp. 1307-1322.

Ulrich, W. (2013a). Reflections on reflective practice (6c/7): Discourse ethics and deliberative democracy, or the difficult path to communicative practice – Habermas 3 (1st half). Ulrich's Bimonthly, May-June 2013.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_may2013.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_may2013.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2013b). Critical systems thinking. In S. Gass and M. Fu (eds.), Encyclopedia of Operations Research and Management Science, 3rd edn. (2 vols). New York: Springer, Vol. 1, pp. 314-326.

Ulrich, W. (2013c). The rational, the moral, and the general: an exploration. Part 1: Introduction, discourse ethics. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2013.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2013.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2013.pdf.

Ulrich, W. (2014a). The rational, the moral, and the general: an exploration. Part 2: Kant's ideas of reason. Ulrich's Bimonthly, January-February 2014.
[HTML]
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_january2014.html
[PDF]
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_january2014.pdf.

Ulrich, W. (2014b). The rational, the moral, and the general: an exploration. Part 3: Approximating ideas – towards critical contextualism. Ulrich's Bimonthly, July-August 2014.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_july2014.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_july2014.pdf

Ulrich, W. (2014c). The rational, the moral, and the general: an exploration. Part 4: Ideas in Ancient Indian Thought / Introduction. Ulrich's Bimonthly, September-October 2014.
[HTML] 
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_september2014.html
[PDF] 
http://wulrich.com/downloads/bimonthly_september2014.

Ulrich, W. (in prep.). Reflections on reflective practice (6d/7): Discourse ethics and deliberative democracy, or the difficult path to communicative practice – Habermas 3 (2nd half). Ulrich's Bimonthly (in prep.).

Vester, F. (2007). The Art of Interconnected Thinking: Tools and Concepts for a New Approach to Tackling Complexity. Munich, Germany: MCB Verlag (German orig.: Die Kunst vernetzt zu denken, Stuttgart, Germany, Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt 1999).

Weber, M. (1958). The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism. Transl. and ed. by H.H. Gerth and D. Martindale. Glencoe, IL: Free Press (reprint edn. Dehli: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1995).

Whitney, W.D. (1885). The Roots, Verbs, and Primary Derivatives of the Sanskrit Language. Leipzig, Germany: Breitkopf and Härtel, and London: Trübner & Co.
[HTML] https://openlibrary.org/books/OL14040083M/The_roots_verb-forms_and_primary_derivatives_of_the_Sanskrit_language.
(facsimile edn.).

Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

 

 

November 2014

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
 
  
  
 
 
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 

December 2014

Su
Mo
Tu
We
Th
Fr
Sa
 
1
2
 3
 4
 5
 6
 7
 8
 9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 

 

 

Picture data  Digital photograph taken on 29 January 2007, around 6:30 p.m., at Lake Geneva, Switzerland. ISO 50, exposure mode program shift, aperture f/4.5, exposure time 1/400 seconds, exposure bias 0, metering mode multi-segment, contrast normal, saturation normal, sharpness normal. Focal length 19 mm (equivalent to 85 mm with a conventional 35 mm camera). Original resolution 2272 x 1704 pixels; current resolution 700 x 525 pixels, compressed to 240 KB.

November-December, 2014

Atman's jagat, 'or: seeking to know brahman'

 Atman's jagat, or 'seeking to know brahman' (grappling with this and that world) 

Brahman satyam, jagat mithya.
"Brahman is the real reality, the world is deceptive.”

(Adi Shankara, 8th/9th century, cited in Bowker, 2000, p. 96)

Notepad for capturing personal thoughts  »

Previous Picture

Next Picture  

Personal notes:

Write down your thoughts before you forget them!
Just be sure to copy them elsewhere before leaving this page.

 

 

 

 

 

 

Last updated 15 Oct 2015 (missing reference added); 22 Dec 2014 (text, first published 16 Nov 2014)
http://wulrich.com/bimonthly_november2014.html

 

 

 

.